header logo image


Page 1,167«..1020..1,1661,1671,1681,169..1,1801,190..»

Cell Therapy Ltd

October 25th, 2015 6:41 pm

Founded in 2009 by Nobel prize winner Professor Sir Martin Evans and Ajan Reginald, former Global Head of Emerging Technologies at Roche, CTL develops life-saving and life altering regenerative medicines. CTLs team of scientists, physicians, and experienced management have discovered and developed a pipeline of world-class regenerative medicines.

Sir Martin Evans' unique expertise in discovering rare stem cells led to CTLs innovative drug discovery engine that can uniquely isolate very rare and potent tissue specific stem cells. This exceptional class of cells is then engineered into unique disease-specific cellular regenerative medicines. Each medicine is disease specific and forms part of CTLs world-class portfolio of four off the shelf blockbuster medicines all scheduled for launch before 2020.

The products in late stage clinical trials include Heartcel which regenerates the damaged heart of adults with coronary artery malformations and children with Kawasaki Disease and Bland White Garland Syndrome. In 2014, Heartcel reported unprecedented heart regeneration clinical trial results and is scheduled to launch in 2018 to treat ~400,000 patients worldwide. Myocardion is in Phase II/III trials and treats mild-moderate heart failure affecting 10 million patients worldwide. Tendoncel is the worlds first topical regenerative medicine, for early intervention of severe tendon injuries, and has completed Phase II trials. It is designed to treat the >1 million severe tendon injuries each year in the US and Europe. Skincel is for skin regeneration, and is due to complete Phase II trials in 2015. It is designed to address ulceration and wrinkles.

CTL combines world-class science and management expertise to bring life-saving regenerative medicines to market.

European Society of Gene and Cell Therapy Congress, 17-20 September 2015, Helsinki,Finland (ESGCT 2015)

4th International Conference and Exhibition on Cell & Gene Therapy, August 10-12, 2015, London (CGT 2015)

The International Society for Stem Cell Research Annual Meeting, 24th-27th June 2015, Stockholm, Sweden (ISSCR 2015)

British Society for Gene and Cell Therapy Annual Conference, 9th-11th June 2015, Strathclyde, Glasgow (BSGCT 2015)

Read more from the original source:
Cell Therapy Ltd

Read More...

Genetic Anti-Aging and Health: Creating REAL Results by …

October 24th, 2015 3:45 pm

Our Genetic Anti-Aging Products & Technologies Deal with the Sources of Aging as well as the Signs of Aging by Addressing theREALCause of Looking Older Your Genes.

Everyone gets older but nobody wants to look or feel older; wrinkles, jowls, puffiness, double chin, bat wings, no energy, foggy mind, loss of sexual desire and ability to perform tasks that you used to with little or no effort. The reason you are losing your vitality and looking older is because the genes responsible for your youthful looks and feeling slow down their activity year after year.

With our Genetic Solutions to Aging and Longevity, you no longer need to be a victim to your genes. The Science of Genetic Anti-Aging , (click to read more) has changed everything about how we look and feel as we age!

All the following Genetic Anti-Aging Products contain the ageLOC technology which is THE Genetic Solution to aging and longevity. We invite you to join us in the ReGeneration of anti-aging and longevity!

Posted by Angela Sladen on Jan 17, 2012 in Genetic Anti Aging Products | 0 comments

(more)

Posted by Angela Sladen on Jan 9, 2012 in Genetic Anti Aging Products, Longevity, Supplements, Top Selling Anti-Aging Products, Weight Management | 0 comments

(more)

Posted by Angela Sladen on Jan 9, 2012 in Genetic Anti Aging Products, SkinCare, Top Selling Anti-Aging Products | 0 comments

Nothing will improve your youthful appearance more than your own genetics and how your genetics express themselves. Consider twins. A set of twins can look exactly the same when they are young but drastically different when they are older. Why? Because of the way their individual genetics express themselves. You now have the power to increase your genetics ability to express itself as it did when you were younger: smooth skin, wrinkle-free, no age spots, small pores and brilliance.

(more)

Posted by Angela Sladen on Jan 9, 2012 in Body Care, Genetic Anti Aging Products, SkinCare, Top Selling Anti-Aging Products | 0 comments

(more)

Follow this link:
Genetic Anti-Aging and Health: Creating REAL Results by ...

Read More...

Ethics of Stem Cell Research (Stanford Encyclopedia of …

October 24th, 2015 3:45 pm

The potential therapeutic benefits of HESC research provide strong grounds in favor of the research. If looked at from a strictly consequentialist perspective, it's almost certainly the case that the potential health benefits from the research outweigh the loss of embryos involved and whatever suffering results from that loss for persons who want to protect embryos. However, most of those who oppose the research argue that the constraints against killing innocent persons to promote social utility apply to human embryos. Thus, as long as we accept non-consequentialist constraints on killing persons, those supporting HESC research must respond to the claim that those constraints apply to human embryos.

In its most basic form, the central argument supporting the claim that it is unethical to destroy human embryos goes as follows: It is morally impermissible to intentionally kill innocent human beings; the human embryo is an innocent human being; therefore it is morally impermissible to intentionally kill the human embryo. It is worth noting that this argument, if sound, would not suffice to show that all or even most HESC research is impermissible, since most investigators engaged in HESC research do not participate in the derivation of HESCs but instead use cell lines that researchers who performed the derivation have made available. To show that researchers who use but do not derive HESCs participate in an immoral activity, one would further need to establish their complicity in the destruction of embryos. We will consider this issue in section 2. But for the moment, let us address the argument that it is unethical to destroy human embryos.

A premise of the argument against killing embryos is that human embryos are human beings. The issue of when a human being begins to exist is, however, a contested one. The standard view of those who oppose HESC research is that a human being begins to exist with the emergence of the one-cell zygote at fertilization. At this stage, human embryos are said to be whole living member[s] of the species homo sapiens [which] possess the epigenetic primordia for self-directed growth into adulthood, with their determinateness and identity fully intact (George & Gomez-Lobo 2002, 258). This view is sometimes challenged on the grounds that monozygotic twinning is possible until around days 1415 of an embryo's development (Smith & Brogaard 2003). An individual who is an identical twin cannot be numerically identical to the one-cell zygote, since both twins bear the same relationship to the zygote, and numerical identity must satisfy transitivity. That is, if the zygote, A, divides into two genetically identical cell groups that give rise to identical twins B and C, B and C cannot be the same individual as A because they are not numerically identical with each other. This shows that not all persons can correctly assert that they began their life as a zygote. However, it does not follow that the zygote is not a human being, or that it has not individuated. This would follow only if one held that a condition of an entity's status as an individual human being is that it be impossible for it to cease to exist by dividing into two or more entities. But this seems implausible. Consider cases in which we imagine adult humans undergoing fission (for example, along the lines of Parfit's thought experiments, where each half of the brain is implanted into a different body) (Parfit 1984). The prospect of our going out of existence through fission does not pose a threat to our current status as distinct human persons. Likewise, one might argue, the fact that a zygote may divide does not create problems for the view that the zygote is a distinct human being.

There are, however, other grounds on which some have sought to reject that the early human embryo is a human being. According to one view, the cells that comprise the early embryo are a bundle of homogeneous cells that exist in the same membrane but do not form a human organism because the cells do not function in a coordinated way to regulate and preserve a single life (Smith & Brogaard 2003, McMahan 2002). While each of the cells is alive, they only become parts of a human organism when there is substantial cell differentiation and coordination, which occurs around day-16 after fertilization. Thus, on this account, disaggregating the cells of the 5-day embryo to derive HESCs does not entail the destruction of a human being.

This account is subject to dispute on empirical grounds. That there is some intercellular coordination in the zygote is revealed by the fact that the development of the early embryo requires that some cells become part of the trophoblast while others become part of the inner cell mass. Without some coordination between the cells, there would be nothing to prevent all cells from differentiating in the same direction (Damschen, Gomez-Lobo and Schonecker 2006). The question remains, though, whether this degree of cellular interaction is sufficient to render the early human embryo a human being. Just how much intercellular coordination must exist for a group of cells to constitute a human organism cannot be resolved by scientific facts about the embryo, but is instead an open metaphysical question (McMahan 2007a).

Suppose that the 5-day human embryo is a human being. On the standard argument against HESC research, membership in the species Homo sapiens confers on the embryo a right not to be killed. This view is grounded in the assumption that human beings have the same moral status (at least with respect to possessing this right) at all stages of their lives.

Some accept that the human embryo is a human being but argue that the human embryo does not have the moral status requisite for a right to life. There is reason to think that species membership is not the property that determines a being's moral status. We have all been presented with the relevant thought experiments, courtesy of Disney, Orwell, Kafka, and countless science fiction works. The results seem clear: we regard mice, pigs, insects, aliens, and so on, as having the moral status of persons in those possible worlds in which they exhibit the psychological and cognitive traits that we normally associate with mature human beings. This suggests that it is some higher-order mental capacity (or capacities) that grounds the right to life. While there is no consensus about the capacities that are necessary for the right to life, some of the capacities that have been proposed include reasoning, self-awareness, and agency (Kuhse & Singer 1992, Tooley 1983, Warren 1973).

The main difficulty for those who appeal to such mental capacities as the touchstone for the right to life is that early human infants lack these capacities, and do so to a greater degree than many of the nonhuman animals that most deem it acceptable to kill (Marquis 2002). This presents a challenge for those who hold that the non-consequentialist constraints on killing human children and adults apply to early human infants. Some reject that these constraints apply to infants, and allow that there may be circumstances where it is permissible to sacrifice infants for the greater good (McMahan 2007b). Others argue that, while infants do not have the intrinsic properties that ground a right to life, we should nonetheless treat them as if they have a right to life in order to promote love and concern towards them, as these attitudes have good consequences for the persons they will become (Benn 1973, Strong 1997).

Some claim that we can reconcile the ascription of a right to life to all humans with the view that higher order mental capacities ground the right to life by distinguishing between two senses of mental capacities: immediately exercisable capacities and basic natural capacities. (George and Gomez-Lobo 2002, 260). According to this view, an individual's immediately exercisable capacity for higher mental functions is the actualization of natural capacities for higher mental functions that exist at the embryonic stage of life. Human embryos have a rational nature, but that nature is not fully realized until individuals are able to exercise their capacity to reason. The difference between these types of capacity is said to be a difference between degrees of development along a continuum. There is merely a quantitative difference between the mental capacities of embryos, fetuses, infants, children, and adults (as well as among infants, children, and adults). And this difference, so the argument runs, cannot justify treating some of these individuals with moral respect while denying it to others.

Given that a human embryo cannot reason at all, the claim that it has a rational nature has struck some as tantamount to asserting that it has the potential to become an individual that can engage in reasoning (Sagan & Singer 2007). But an entity's having this potential does not logically entail that it has the same status as beings that have realized some or all of their potential (Feinberg 1986). Moreover, with the advent of cloning technologies, the range of entities that we can now identify as potential persons arguably creates problems for those who place great moral weight on the embryo's potential. A single somatic cell or HESC can in principle (though not yet in practice) develop into a mature human being under the right conditionsthat is, where the cell's nucleus is transferred into an enucleated egg, the new egg is electrically stimulated to create an embryo, and the embryo is transferred to a woman's uterus and brought to term. If the basis for protecting embryos is that they have the potential to become reasoning beings, then, some argue, we have reason to ascribe a high moral status to the trillions of cells that share this potential and to assist as many of these cells as we reasonably can to realize their potential (Sagan & Singer 2007, Savulescu 1999). Because this is a stance that we can expect nearly everyone to reject, it's not clear that opponents of HESC research can effectively ground their position in the human embryo's potential.

One response to this line of argument has been to claim that embryos possess a kind of potential that somatic cells and HESCs lack. An embryo has potential in the sense of having an active disposition and intrinsic power to develop into a mature human being (Lee & George 2006). An embryo can mature on its own in the absence of interference with its development. A somatic cell, on the other hand, does not have the inherent capacity or disposition to grow into a mature human being. However, some question whether this distinction is viable, especially in the HESC research context. While it is true that somatic cells can realize their potential only with the assistance of outside interventions, an embryo's development also requires that numerous conditions external to it are satisfied. In the case of embryos that are naturally conceived, they must implant, receive nourishment, and avoid exposure to dangerous substances in utero. In the case of spare embryos created through in vitro fertilizationwhich are presently the source of HESCs for researchthe embryos must be thawed and transferred to a willing woman's uterus. Given the role that external factorsincluding technological interventionsplay in an embryo's realizing its potential, one can question whether there is a morally relevant distinction between an embryo's and somatic cell's potential and thus raise doubts about potentiality as a foundation for the right to life (Devolder & Harris 2007).

Some grant that human embryos lack the properties essential to a right to life, but hold that they possess an intrinsic value that calls for a measure of respect and places at least some moral constraints on their use: The life of a single human organism commands respect and protection no matter in what form or shape, because of the complex creative investment it represents and because of our wonder at the divine or evolutionary processes that produce new lives from old ones. (Dworkin l992, 84). There are, however, divergent views about the level of respect embryos command and what limits exist on their use. Some opponents of HESC research hold that the treatment of human embryos as mere research tools always fails to manifest proper respect for them. Other opponents take a less absolutist view. Some, for example, deem embryos less valuable than more mature human beings but argue that the benefits of HESC research are too speculative to warrant the destruction of embryos, and that the benefits might, in any case, be achieved through the use of noncontroversial sources of stem cells (e.g., adult stem cells) (Holm 2003).

Many, if not most, who support the use of human embryos for HESC research would likely agree with opponents of the research that there are some circumstances where the use of human embryos would display a lack of appropriate respect for human life, for example, were they to be offered for consumption to contestants in a reality TV competition or destroyed for the production of cosmetics. But proponents of the research hold that the value of human embryos is not great enough to constrain the pursuit of research that may yield significant therapeutic benefits. Supporters of the research also frequently question whether most opponents of the research are consistent in their ascription of a high value to human embryos, as opponents generally display little concern about the fact that many embryos created for fertility treatment are discarded.

When spare embryos exist after fertility treatment, the individuals for whom the embryos were created typically have the option of storing for them for future reproductive use, donating them to other infertile couples, donating them to research, or discarding them. Some argue that as long as the decision to donate embryos for research is made after the decision to discard them, it is morally permissible to use them in HESC research even if we assume that they have the moral status of persons. The claim takes two different forms. One is that it is morally permissible to kill an individual who is about to be killed by someone else where killing that individual will help others (Curzer, H. 2004). The other is that researchers who derive HESCs from embryos that were slated for destruction do not cause their death. Instead, the decision to discard the embryos causes their death; research just causes the manner of their death (Green 2002).

Both versions of the argument presume that the decision to discard spare embryos prior to the decision to donate them to research entails that donated embryos are doomed to destruction when researchers receive them. There are two arguments one might marshal against this presumption. First, one who wants to donate embryos to research might first elect to discard them only because doing so is a precondition for donating them. There could be cases in which one who chooses the discard option would have donated the embryos to other couples were the research donation option not available. The fact that a decision to discard embryos is made prior to the decision to donate the embryos thus does not establish that the embryos were doomed to destruction before the decision to donate them to research was made. Second, a researcher who receives embryos could choose to rescue them, whether by continuing to store them or by donating them to infertile couples. While this would violate the law, the fact that it is within a researcher's power to prevent the destruction of the embryos he or she receives poses problems for the claim that the decision to discard the embryos dooms them or causes their destruction.

Assume for the sake of argument that it is morally impermissible to destroy human embryos. It does not follow that all research with HESCs is impermissible, as it is sometimes permissible to benefit from moral wrongs. For example, there is nothing objectionable about transplant surgeons and patients benefiting from the organs of murder and drunken driving victims (Robertson 1988). If there are conditions under which a researcher may use HESCs without being complicit in the destruction of embryos, then those who oppose the destruction of embryos could support research with HESCs under certain circumstances.

Researchers using HESCs are clearly implicated in the destruction of embryos where they derive the cells themselves or enlist others to derive the cells. However, most investigators who conduct research with HESCs obtain them from an existing pool of cell lines and play no role in their derivation. One view is that we cannot assign causal or moral responsibility to investigators for the destruction of embryos from which the HESCs they use are derived where their research plans had no effect on whether the original immoral derivation occurred. (Robertson 1999). This view requires qualification. There may be cases in which HESCs are derived for the express purpose of making them widely available to HESC investigators. In such instances, it may be that no individual researcher's plans motivated the derivation of the cells. Nonetheless, one might argue that investigators who use these cells are complicit in the destruction of the embryos from which the cells were derived because they are participants in a research enterprise that creates a demand for HESCs. For these investigators to avoid the charge of complicity in the destruction of embryos, it must be the case that the researchers who derived the HESCs would have performed the derivation in the absence of external demand for the cells (Siegel 2004).

The issue about complicity goes beyond the question of an HESC researcher's role in the destruction of the particular human embryo(s) from which the cells he or she uses are derived. There is a further concern that research with existing HESCs will result in the future destruction of embryos: [I]f this research leads to possible treatments, private investment in such efforts will increase greatly and the demand for many thousands of cell lines with different genetic profiles will be difficult to resist. (U.S. Conference of Catholic Bishops 2001). This objection faces two difficulties. First, it appears to be too sweeping: research with adult stem cells and non-human animal stem cells, as well as general research in genetics, embryology, and cell biology could be implicated, since all of this research might advance our understanding of HESCs and result in increased demand for them. Yet, no one, including those who oppose HESC research, argues that we should not support these areas of research. Second, the claim about future demand for HESCs is speculative. Indeed, current HESC research could ultimately reduce or eliminate demand for the cells by providing insights into cell biology that enable the use of alternative sources of cells (Siegel 2004).

While it might thus be possible for a researcher to use HESCs without being morally responsible for the destruction of human embryos, that does not end the inquiry into complicity. Some argue that agents can be complicit in wrongful acts for which they are not morally responsible. One such form of complicity arises from an association with wrongdoing that symbolizes acquiescence in the wrongdoing (Burtchaell 1989). The failure to take appropriate measures to distance oneself from moral wrongs may give rise to metaphysical guilt, which produces a moral taint and for which shame is the appropriate response (May 1992). The following question thus arises: Assuming it is morally wrongful to destroy human embryos, are HESC researchers who are not morally responsible for the destruction of embryos complicit in the sense of symbolically aligning themselves with a wrongful act?

One response is that a researcher who benefits from the destruction of embryos need not sanction the act any more than the transplant surgeon who uses the organs of a murder or drunken driving victim sanctions the homicidal act (Curzer 2004). But this response is unlikely to be satisfactory to opponents of HESC research. There is arguably an important difference between the transplant case and HESC research insofar as the moral wrong associated with the latter (a) systematically devalues a particular class of human beings and (b) is largely socially accepted and legally permitted. Opponents of HESC research might suggest that the HESC research case is more analogous to the following kind of case: Imagine a society in which the practice of killing members of a particular racial or ethnic group is legally permitted and generally accepted. Suppose that biological materials obtained from these individuals subsequent to their deaths are made available for research uses. Could researchers use these materials while appropriately distancing themselves from the wrongful practice? Arguably, they could not. There is a heightened need to protest moral wrongs where those wrongs are socially and legally accepted. Attempts to benefit from the moral wrong in these circumstances may be incompatible with mounting a proper protest (Siegel 2003).

But even if we assume that HESC researchers cannot avoid the taint of metaphysical guilt, it is not clear that researchers who bear no moral responsibility for the destruction of embryos are morally obligated not to use HESCs. One might argue that there is a prima facie duty to avoid moral taint, but that this duty may be overridden for the sake of a noble cause.

Most HESCs are derived from embryos that were created for infertility treatment but that were in excess of what the infertile individual(s) ultimately needed to achieve a pregnancy. The HESCs derived from these leftover embryos offer investigators a powerful tool for understanding the mechanisms controlling cell differentiation. However, there are scientific and therapeutic reasons not to rely entirely on leftover embryos. From a research standpoint, creating embryos through cloning technologies with cells that are known to have particular genetic mutations would allow researchers to study the underpinnings of genetic diseases in vitro. From a therapeutic standpoint, the HESCs obtained from leftover IVF embryos are not genetically diverse enough to address the problem of immune rejection by recipients of stem cell transplants. (Induced pluripotent stem cells may ultimately prove sufficient for these research and therapeutic ends, since the cells can (a) be selected for specific genetic mutations and (b) provide an exact genetic match for stem cell recipients.) At present, the best way to address the therapeutic problem is through the creation of a public stem cell bank that represents a genetically diverse pool of stem cell lines (Faden et al. 2003, Lott & Savulescu 2007). This kind of stem cell bank would require the creation of embryos from gamete donors who share the same HLA-types (i.e., similar versions of the genes that mediate immune recognition and rejection).

Each of these enterprises has its own set of ethical issues. In the case of research cloning, some raise concerns, for example, that the perfection of cloning techniques for research purposes will enable the pursuit of reproductive cloning, and that efforts to obtain the thousands of eggs required for the production of cloned embryos will result in the exploitation of women who provide the eggs (President's Council on Bioethics 2002, Norsigian 2005). With respect to stem cell banks, it is not practically possible to create a bank of HESCs that will provide a close immunological match for all recipients. This gives rise to the challenge of determining who will have biological access to stem cell therapies. We might construct the bank so that it provides matches for the greatest number of people in the population, gives everyone an equal chance of finding a match, or ensures that all ancestral/ethnic groups are fairly represented in the bank (Faden et al. 2003, Bok, Schill, & Faden 2004, Greene 2006).

There are, however, more general challenges to the creation of embryos for research and therapeutic purposes. Some argue that the creation of embryos for non-reproductive ends is morally problematic, regardless of whether they are created through cloning or in vitro fertilization. There are two related arguments that have been advanced to morally distinguish the creation of embryos for reproductive purposes from the creation of embryos for research and therapeutic purposes. First, each embryo created for procreative purposes is originally viewed as a potential child in the sense that each is a candidate for implantation and development into a mature human. In contrast, embryos created for research or therapies are viewed as mere tools from the outset (Annas, Caplan & Elias 1996, President's Council on Bioethics 2002). Second, while embryos created for research and therapy are produced with the intent to destroy them, the destruction of embryos created for reproduction is a foreseeable but unintended consequence of their creation (FitzPatrick 2003).

One response to the first argument has been to suggest that we could, under certain conditions, view all research embryos as potential children in the relevant sense. If all research embryos were included in a lottery in which some of them were donated to individuals for reproductive purposes, all research embryos would have a chance at developing into mature humans (Devander 2005). Since those who oppose creating embryos for research would likely maintain their opposition in the research embryo lottery case, it is arguably irrelevant whether embryos are viewed as potential children when they are created. Of course, research embryos in the lottery case would be viewed as both potential children and potential research tools. But this is also true in the case of embryos created for reproductive purposes where patients are open to donating spare embryos to research.

As to the second argument, the distinction between intending and merely foreseeing harms is one to which many people attach moral significance, and it is central to the Doctrine of Double Effect. But even if one holds that this is a morally significant distinction, it is not clear that it is felicitous to characterize the destruction of spare embryos as an unintended but foreseeable side-effect of creating embryos for fertility treatment. Fertility clinics do not merely foresee that some embryos will be destroyed, as they choose to offer patients the option of discarding embryos and carry out the disposal of embryos when patients request it. Patients who elect that their embryos be discarded also do not merely foresee the embryos' destruction; their election of that option manifests their intention that the embryos be destroyed. There is thus reason to doubt that there is a moral distinction between creating embryos for research and creating them for reproductive purposes, at least given current fertility clinic practices.

Recent scientific work suggests it is possible to derive gametes from human pluripotent stem cells. Researchers have generated sperm and eggs from mouse ESCs and iPSCs and have used these stem cell-derived gametes to produce offspring (Hayashi 2011; Hayashi 2012). While it may take several years before researchers succeed in deriving gametes from human stem cells, the research holds much promise for basic science and clinical application. For example, the research could provide important insights into the fundamental processes of gamete biology, assist in the understanding of genetic disorders, and provide otherwise infertile individuals a means of creating genetically related children. The ability to derive gametes from human stem cells could also reduce or eliminate the need for egg donors and thus help overcome concerns about exploitation of donors and the risks involved in egg retrieval. Nonetheless, the research gives rise to some controversial issues related to embryos, genetics, and assisted reproductive technologies (D. Mathews et al. 2009).

One issue arises from the fact that some research on stem cell-derived gametes requires the creation of embryos, regardless of whether one is using ESCs or iPSCs. To establish that a particular technique for deriving human gametes from stem cells produces functional sperm and eggs, it is necessary to demonstrate that the cells can produce an embryo. This entails the creation of embryos through in vitro fertilization. Since it would not be safe to implant embryos created during the early stages of the research, the likely disposition of the embryos is that they would be destroyed. In such instances, the research would implicate all of the moral issues surrounding the creation and destruction of embryos for research. However, the creation of embryos for research in this situation would not necessitate the destruction of the embryos, as it does when embryos are created to derive stem cell lines. One could in principle store them indefinitely rather than destroy them. This would still leave one subject to the objection that life is being created for instrumental purposes. But the force of the objection is questionable since it is not clear that this instrumental use is any more objectionable than the routine and widely accepted practice of creating excess IVF embryos in the reproductive context to increase the probability of generating a sufficient number of viable ones to produce a pregnancy.

Further issues emerge with the prospect of being able to produce large quantities of eggs from stem cells. As the capacity to identify disease and non-disease related alleles through preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD) expands, the ability to create large numbers of embryos would substantially increase the chances of finding an embryo that possesses most or all of the traits one wishes to select. This would be beneficial in preventing the birth of children with genetic diseases. But matters would become morally contentious if it were possible to select for non-disease characteristics, such as sexual orientation, height, superior intelligence, memory, and musical ability. One common argument against using PGD in this way is that it could devalue the lives of those who do not exhibit the chosen characteristics. Another concern is that employing PGD to select for non-disease traits would fail to acknowledge the giftedness of life by treating children as objects of our design or products of our will or instruments of our ambition rather accepting them as they are given to us (Sandel 2004, 56). There is additionally a concern about advances in genetics heightening inequalities where certain traits confer social and economic advantages and only the well-off have the resources to access the technology (Buchanan 1995). Of course, one can question whether the selection of non-disease traits would in fact lead to devaluing other characteristics, whether it would alter the nature of parental love, or whether it is distinct enough from currently permitted methods of gaining social and economic advantage to justify regulating the practice. Nonetheless, the capacity to produce human stem cell-derived gametes would make these issues more pressing.

Follow this link:
Ethics of Stem Cell Research (Stanford Encyclopedia of ...

Read More...

Ethical Issues and Risk Assessment in Biotechnology

October 24th, 2015 3:45 pm

Bioindustry: A Description of California's Bioindustry and Summary of the Public Issues Affecting Its Development By Gus A. Koehler, PhD. Return to table of contents There is a rich public debate about how the potential risks associated with biotechnology methods and bioindustry products should be assessed and about whether and how bioethics should influence public policy. A general structure for guiding public policy discourse is emerging but is not fully developed. Groups perceive risks differently depending on their culture, scientific background, perception of government, and other factors. Expert opinion supports a range of positions. 194 Deeply and honestly held but often conflicting beliefs and values about nature, animals, and the community good animate the debate. The result is that biotechnology issues are often highly contentious and debated on both scientific and ethical grounds. Two contemporary examples are:

Biotechnology's risks are sometimes purely conjectural. Without research and clinical trials, risks cannot be fully assessed. Yet conjectural and ethical issues are important because biotechnology affects not only human practices and economic sectors, but also medical practices and the relationship between humanity, animals and the environment. In Paul Thompson's view,

Public Policy Debate

There are many complex and emotionally charged ethical issues that the development of biotechnology poses for the first time or reframes. This paper can only touch on some of them. Federal and state governments are attempting to grapple with these issues and create a framework to deal with them.

Three Federal panels addressed bioethical issues prior to 1983:

These federal panels had a major impact on bioethical debate and risk assessment. For example, the President's Commission:

Except for the National Institutes of Health-Department of Energy Working Group on Ethical, Legal, and Social Implications of the Human Genome Project, bioethical issues have been analyzed since 1983 on an ad hoc basis by temporary panels leading to delayed discussions, restricted scope, and inconsistent policy positions between panels. Congressional attempts to create a new national commission in 1990 to examine bioethical issues were unsuccessful, primarily due to a highly contentious debate over fetal research.

Bioethics examines broad issues such as animal rights and welfare, human testing, and the potential effects of genetically engineered species on other species and the environment. Risk assessments analyze the relative risks posed by possible toxic, pathogenic, and ecological effects of biotechnology and bioindustry. There are three broad analytical approaches to risk assessment:

States and the federal government generally focus on the second approach, the characteristics and environmental risks of the altered organism, and not on the processes used to produce it or on possible natural rights. This "organism-in the environment" approach to risk assessment involves evaluation of any of the following: 199

The science of developing transgenic animals is just beginning. Critics contend that it raises both animal physiological (possible loss of function or generation of deformities) or psychological problems (unacceptable levels of stress or loss of function) and associated ethical issues. A 1989 statement, "Consultation on Respect for Life and the Environment," signed by the National Council of Churches, the Foundation on Economic Trends, and the Center for the Respect of Life and the Environment, called for a moratorium on transgenic animal research. The statement asserted that such technology "portends fundamental changes in the public's perception of, and attitude towards animals, which would be regarded as human creations, inventions, and commodities, rather than God's creation and subjects of nature." 200 For example, during their development transgenic swine had many serious problems:

Should we understand animal well-being to include an animal's entitlement to certain key traits that it would be unethical to select against or to seriously weaken? 202 Should transgenic animal research and use be restricted to certain species? 203 How are each of these questions to be reconciled with potential improvements in human health that could result from such research?

In contrast, the U.S. Department of Agriculture, the Biotechnology Industry Organization, and the American Medical Association argue that the creation of altered animals is medically and economically beneficial for humans and should continue.

Is the legal status of a transgenic animal that is owned by its creating company different from a domesticated animal? How do existing animal welfare statutes (humane treatment) apply to such animals? Each of these issues are magnified by the emerging ability to mass-produce large numbers of bioengineered animals such as genetically identical sheep and cattle that could become a primary source of fiber and food.

The deliberate manipulation of the gene line to achieve desirable human characteristics by altering sperm genes or to inserting genes from other species into human sex cells also has serious ethical implications. For example, is it ethical to make inheritable changes in the human genome affecting the characteristics of individuals that would be born with it? Who has the right to make a genetic therapy decision involving a fetus, children, or other? Should such guidelines extend to fetuses not brought to term for experimental purposes? 204 Some of these issues may be addressed in guidelines being developed by the National Institutes of Health.

In May 1995, a large coalition of religious leaders--Catholic bishops, Protestant and Jewish leaders and groups of Muslims, Hindus and Buddhists--announced its opposition to patents on human and animal life. The coalition did not oppose genetic engineering or biotechnology, but rather patenting human genes or organisms. It contends that such patents violate the sanctity of human life and reduce the "blueprint of evolution" to a marketable commodity. The group argues that life is a gift from God that should be cherished and nurtured. To reduce life to a commodity is to turn it into a product that can be owned and manipulated for profit alone, according to the group. 205

A second broad coalition of U.S. and international indigenous peoples, consumer, environmental, and other non-government groups issued the "Blue Mountain Declaration" in June 1995, declaring, in part,

This group also strongly opposes federal funding for the Human Genome Diversity Project. In particular, it is concerned about gathering samples of human genetic material from indigenous communities around the world. Related issues include ownership of cell lines, informed consent before providing the sample, patenting of genetic sequences, and who should benefit from the sale of related products.

Counter arguments are presented in the patenting (p. 38), human biological materials ownership (p. 41), and human and animal related products (p. 3-1) portions of this paper. These issues are currently under consideration by the courts and various professional organizations. Generally, the trend appears to be in the direction of allowing private ownership of laboratory-created organisms and the continued collection of human genetic material, on the grounds that the results are beneficial to humanity.

Organ transplants and the availability of embryological tissue for research are important and difficult issues for modern medicine. Many lives are prolonged or saved every year through organ transplants. The National Organ Transplantation Act prohibits the sale of human tissue and organs for transplantation. This prohibition does not apply to non-transplantation purposes, including the sale of organs and other parts, such as embryological tissue, for research. 207

Fetal organs and tissue are believed by some researchers to be essential to research that might lead to alleviation of Parkinson's disease, diabetes, and other serious illnesses.

The federal government banned federally funded human embryology research for 15 years, (1979 to 1994), although some research continued with private funding. President Clinton has ordered that no federal funds be spent on embryos created for research. 208 However, the order did not specifically forbid support for research on human embryos.

The National Institutes of Health convened an ad hoc Human Embryo Research Panel to examine the issue of embryo research. In 1994, the panel found that such research could make substantial contributions and agreed that pre-implantation embryos should receive serious moral consideration but not to the same degree as infants and children. The panel restricted its attention to research on pre-implantation embryos, or multi-cell clusters that are less than 14 days old and that are without a definite nerve system. The panel recommended an advisory process similar to that being followed for gene therapy, and contended that federal funding would help to establish consistent public review of the research. 209

Researchers obtain fetal tissue from hospitals and clinics. Some clinics have developed an informed consent form for patients giving permission to use fetal tissue from an aborted fetus for research or organ transplant. However, one author contends that, "there has been virtually no effective policing of fetal organ harvesting by the federal government or any state agency," and that such appears unlikely. 210

Animal to Human Organ Transplants

The area of organ transplants from animals to humans is developing so rapidly that the National Academy of Science's Institute of Medicine has created a committee to examine the practice. 211 Issues that the Institute will examine include, "How to protect the rights of the first 'pioneer' patients? How to prevent the introduction of dangerous animal pathogens into the human population? And will the public find the idea of transplanting animal organs into humans acceptable?" 212

The FDA has also expressed concerns about animal-to-human transplants. Transplants might allow dangerous pathogens in animals to enter humans. Researchers plan to screen tissues for known viruses and to monitor recipients for infectious disease. However, screening for known viruses may not be adequate to apprehend new pathogens. The FDA wants stricter safeguards that could include improved tests for pathogens, protocols to quarantine patients, and the creation of colonies of "clean" animals. 213

Bioethics and Human Diagnostics

Testing for genetic defects is generally considered to be helpful and to increase possible treatment options. The issue becomes much more complex when genetic information has implications for reproductive choice or portends an unhealthy future for a currently healthy person (for example, having a mastectomy to prevent the potential future occurrence of a genetically-based cancer). Related issues include: disclosure of a genetic defect; availability and affordability of genetic counseling and health insurance; and employee screening. Screening for genetic diseases is controlled by the National Genetic Diseases Act, which provides for research, screening, counseling, and professional education for people with Tay-Sachs disease, Cystic Fibrosis, Huntington's disease, and a number of other conditions in which genetic mutations may be involved.

The use of genetic testing in the workplace can involve genetic screening or genetic monitoring. Screening involves a one-time test to detect a pre-existing trait in a worker or job applicant. Genetic monitoring involves multiple tests of a worker over time to determine if an occupational exposure has induced a genetic change. In 1989 five percent of the Fortune 500 companies surveyed either were using or had used employee genetic monitoring. [214] Genetic monitoring is reliable at the population level, not the individual employee level. There are three principal issues: [215]

The implementation of genetic testing can affect job applicants and workers, employers, and society differently. The impact varies according to whether the test performed is for genetic monitoring for chromosomal damage due to workplace conditions, genetic screening for susceptibilities to occupational illness, or genetic screening for inherited conditions or traits unrelated to the workplace but that could affect health insurance costs. Employees may wish to be genetically tested to track their health status but be concerned that the information could be used to remove them from the workplace, to deny insurance or keep them from being hired. On the other hand, employers contend that they need such information for hiring purposes and may wish to use genetic screening tests, establish conditions for employee participation, and implement consequences. Such employer practices are consistent with existing pre-employment medical testing practices. The Office of Technology Assessment (OTA), after a review of the issues involved, found:

Federal legislation (including the Occupational Safety and Health Act, the Rehabilitation Act of 1973, Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, the National Labor Relations Act, and the Americans with Disabilities Act) provides some protections against genetic testing and screening abuses, particularly against unilateral employer imposition of genetic monitoring and screening, discrimination, and breaches in confidentiality. States have also been active in this area, adopting legislation concerning genetic screening and employment. [217]

The ability to test for possible inherited tendencies such as high blood pressure and other heart-related diseases, diabetes, and cancer has important implications for access to health insurance. Health insurance could become too expensive for some people. In the 1970s some people were denied insurance, charged higher premiums, or denied jobs because they tested positive as carriers of sickle cell anemia (a genetic condition inherited by some African Americans). 218 More recent studies have documented cases of genetic descrimination against healthy persons with a gene that predisposes them or their children to an illness. "In a recent survey of people with a known genetic condition in the family, 22% indicated that they had been refused health insurance coverage because of their genetic status, whether they were sick or not." 219

Genetic information is already requested on health insurance applications. According to a 1992 OTA survey:

Thirteen states have passed genetic testing laws. 221 Most of the laws are narrowly drawn and attempt to prevent discrimination such as denial of insurance or employment because of a genetically identified disease. For example, an Ohio law prohibits insurers from requiring potential clients to submit to genetic tests as a condition of coverage. 222 Recent state actions regarding genetic testing include: 223

In a related decision, "...the U.S. Equal Employment Opportunity Commission has concluded that healthy people carrying abnormal genes are protected against employment discrimination by the Americans with Disabilities Act." 224 The decision seems to limit the use of genetic screening. California Department of Fair Employment and Housing regulations protect employees who have an increased likelihood of developing a physical handicap, but it is not clear whether this rule applies to genetic monitoring.

In January 1995, a new California law took effect prohibiting health insurers from discriminating against an applicant by increasing rates because of genetic traits when the person has no symptoms of any disease or disorder. Insurance companies are also prohibited from requesting or providing genetic information without prior authorization. Chaptered legislation introduced by Senator Johnston in the 1995 session (SB 1020) extends this provision by prohibiting insurance companies from requiring a higher rate or charge or offering or providing different terms, conditions, or benefits on the basis of a person's genetic characteristics. SB 970 (Johnston, 1995) would expand the definition of medical condition under the Department of Fair Employment and Housing to include discrimination against people who have an increased likelihood of developing a physical handicap due to genetic problems.

Federal law limits state protection against insurance coverage genetic discrimination. Self-funded insurance plans are exempted from state law by the federal Employee Retirement Income Security Act. Nationally, about one-third of the non-elderly insured are covered by such plans. In addition, most state laws prohibit discrimination based on genetic tests carried out in a laboratory. However these laws often do not extend that protection to use of genetic information gathered by other methods that trace genetic inheritance or to disclosure of a request to have a genetic test. 225

Recently, the National Action Plan on Breast Cancer and the Working Group on Ethical, Legal, and Social Implications of the Human Genome Project developed a set of recommendations and definitions for state policy makers to protect against genetic discrimination. 226

Genetic counseling services are important to individuals and families for understanding the results of genetic tests. These services also face serious ethical dilemmas. For example, a parent may refuse to share a diagnosis of an inherited tendency for colon cancer with the family, including the children. To honor the patient's request might harm the rest of the family. 227

In 1993, a panel of the National Academy of Sciences concluded that federal oversight of gene testing needs to be improved. 228 The Health Care Financing Administration and the Food and Drug Administration are both responsible for ensuring the quality of testing in commercial laboratories. Currently the Health Care Financing Administration has no specific standards for laboratories that analyze DNA, and inspectors are not trained to evaluate the appropriate execution of DNA tests. The Food and Drug Administration requires that manufacturers obtain approval before marketing laboratory test kits and that laboratories offering experimental genetic tests be cleared and approved by the FDA. 229s

The field testing and release of genetically engineered plants and crops remains controversial but is widespread. Small-scale field tests of genetically-engineered crops have been under way in the U.S. for almost six years. Regulatory standards have been developed, and crops approved for testing and release. Since 1987, the U.S. Department of Agriculture has approved more than 860 applications and notifications to field-test transgenic crops. 230 More than 1,025 field tests of genetically modified plants were conducted in 32 countries between 1986 and 1993. Thirty-eight different plant species with nearly 200 different engineered properties have been tested in the field to date. By the year 2000, there may be as many as 400 different, economically important genetically modified plants under field evaluation. 231

As noted above, the USDA has recently expedited approvals for field-test permits. In 1995, the EPA approved the first pesticidal transgenic plants (corn, potato, and cotton plants) for "limited" commercialization. Approval for full scale production is expected by 1996. 232

The U.S. National Academy of Sciences concluded in 1987, "There is no evidence of the existence of unique hazards either in the use of RDNA techniques or in the movement of genes between unrelated organisms." 233 The U.S. National Research Council agreed: "No conceptual distinction exists between genetic modification of plants and microorganisms by classical methods or by molecular techniques that modify DNA and transfer genes," whether in the laboratory, in the field, or in large-scale environmental introductions. 234

The EPA,

Nevertheless, there is still considerable public disagreement over the implications of introducing genetically-engineered species into the environment for testing or commercial purposes. Critics have been successful at obtaining court injunctions to stop the release of biological materials into the environment. Some scientists and ecologists claim that unlike risk assessment for synthetic chemicals, "there is no commensurate methodology for assessing the risks of released organisms." 236 However, the overall likelihood of harm could rise as the number and variety of crop releases increase. If a problem occurs it could be high-risk with long-term unexpected consequences. Among the possibilities:

There is preliminary evidence that seems to support some of these concerns. Some exchanges of genetic information between plants in the field may occur by way of bacteria 237 or viruses:

Other scientists believe that the problem may not be significant, as "the potential benefits of engineered resistance genes far outweigh the vanishingly small risk of creating new and harmful viruses." 239

In some cases, a permit must be obtained from the USDA to begin limited field testing. The review often includes assessment of whether the product meets federal environmental-assessment standards and the environmental requirements of the Plant Pest Act. The EPA has developed guidelines for evaluating modified microorganisms under the Toxic Substances Control Act and for small-scale field testing of plants that produce pesticides under the Federal Insecticide, Fungicide, and Rodenticide Act. 240 These processes are considered by the respective agencies and industry to be more than adequate for evaluating new organisms, detecting any viral recombination that might create new, potentially high-risk viruses, 241 and for field testing pesticide producing plants.

Regulatory decisions on field testing seriously affect research agendas. For example, after the Environmental Protection Agency refused Monsanto's request to field test a new genetically engineered bacterium to improve plant resistance to frost, the company dismantled its entire research program on microbial biocontrol agents. (Monsanto remains very involved in other biotechnology research areas.) 242

Some ecologists remain concerned about the need for additional information beyond that required by the USDA and EPA on a species' ability to survive, proliferate, and disperse in nature, and about the potential for genetic exchange of materials between species. 243 One analysis concludes,

Jack Dekker and Gary Comstock, of Iowa State University, propose that ethical and technical criteria be developed and included in the regulatory process to address the issue:

Existing field experiments have not resolved the debate. There are conflicting studies with differing answers. These findings show just how complex and unresolved the issue is. For example, one research effort found that transgenic sugar beets could transfer genes to weed relatives. Other evidence indicates that viral RNA or DNA inserted in a plant to make it virus-resistant may combine with genetic material from an invading virus to form new, more virulent strains. But, recent work on the transgenic squash has "found no evidence that wild squash have bred with transgenic plants to form virus-resistant wild squash." 246 Despite concerns expressed by some observers, scientists consider it highly unlikely that the squash's wild relatives could obtain genetically engineered benefits from commercial relatives or that "novel recombinant viruses could crop up from [squashes] infected by wild viruses." 247 It might take a number of unlikely conditions occurring in the environment before new or damaging recombinant viruses could spread. 248 A more recent Danish study found that a commercial crop called oil seed rape containing a herbicide resistant gene can cross-fertilize with a weed called Brassica Campetris. Both plants are from the same mustard family. 249 The bioengineered gene is present in the crossbreeds and is passed on to subsequent generations.

Large scale plantings of transgenic crops might resolve some of these questions:

According to a report in Science, "Chinese scientists have recently launched massive field trials of transgenic tobacco, tomatoes, and rice on thousands of hectares." 251 Scientists in developing countries who are faced with food production problems may take more risks than others, the report notes. 252

Recent research also raises questions about the adequacy of models used to predict the dispersion of genetically engineered plants into the environment.

The possible accidental release of potentially damaging organisms into the environment extends to other organisms as well. For example, efforts by Australian scientists to restrict a deadly virus (used in experiments against wildly proliferating European rabbits) to an off coast island failed. "Officials foresaw little possibility of the virus's escaping from the island, but escape it did." 254

There are inherent conflicts involved in how biotechnology develops as an industry and the way ethical questions and public policy positions are discussed and adopted. Key factors include, for example:

The conflict between the ethical issues that emerge as research proceeds and discoveries are made, and the time and other pressures to immediately move products to the market place create public policy issues that cannot be easily resolved for a number of complex and interacting reasons:

Potential health, economic, and business benefits are huge. The potential human and financial rewards that could emerge from curing serious diseases, increasing the food supply, and substantially extending and improving the quality of human life are very large. It is this possibility that drives researchers, investors, and potential benefactors.

Biotechnology/bioethical issues are not simple. The underlying science is complex, as are the resulting issues. Bioethics is a new field that is developing right along with biotechnology.

It is difficult to know which biotechnology-induced changes in an organism or production technology might result in large scale social or economic changes. The often new relationship of the discovery to the greater environment, human health, marketplace, and to future generations is unknown. The law of unintended consequences is a major concern.

Measurements of the socio-economic and market effects of a new technology are hard to make. Methods for measuring expected human, ecological, industrial, and financial risks, short and long term costs/benefits, and other relevant factors are just being developed. It may be particularly difficult to estimate the long terms costs of biotechnology innovations, given their often unpredictable effects.

There is pressure to achieve immediate short term economic gains that might have essentially unknowable long-term effects. For example, patenting corn, rice, potatoes and wheat and the accompanying farming and marketing methods might reorder the entire agricultural industry and rural life.

Issues are set within conflicting time horizons and value systems. Research and marketing time horizons are relatively short, emphasizing immediate financial pay-off and scientific prestige. In contrast, bioethics and public policy questions often involve a long-term time horizon (generations of people), whole systems (ecological or industry), and the quality of individual and community life.

The definition of what "safe" means and how to evaluate an acceptable level of risk is still evolving. For example, how should manufacturers label bioengineered products and other products that may use genes inserted from plants to which people might be allergic? The large scale availability of genetic testing and its implications for the workplace and for inherited health problems are issues that are just now being addressed.

There is strong competitive pressure to go forward with new and potentially risky technology in a global market. European, Asian and other nations are fiercely competing with each other to develop and dominate a segment of the biotechnology industry, if not the industry itself. As noted, China (page 61), has already embarked on a series of field tests that would probably not be approved in the West.

Next Chapter: Business Needs of Biotechnology

Return to table of contents

Link:
Ethical Issues and Risk Assessment in Biotechnology

Read More...

Kidney transplantation – Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

October 24th, 2015 3:44 pm

Kidney transplantation or renal transplantation is the organ transplant of a kidney into a patient with end-stage renal disease. Kidney transplantation is typically classified as deceased-donor (formerly known as cadaveric) or living-donor transplantation depending on the source of the donor organ. Living-donor renal transplants are further characterized as genetically related (living-related) or non-related (living-unrelated) transplants, depending on whether a biological relationship exists between the donor and recipient. Exchanges and chains are a novel approach to expand the living donor pool.

One of the earliest mentions about the real possibility of a kidney transplant was by American medical researcher Simon Flexner, who declared in a reading of his paper on Tendencies in Pathology in the University of Chicago in 1907 that it would be possible in the then-future for diseased human organs substitution for healthy ones by surgery including arteries, stomach, kidneys and heart.[1]

In 1933 surgeon Yuri Voronoy from Kherson in the Soviet Union attempted the first human kidney transplant, using a kidney removed 6 hours earlier from the deceased donor to be reimplanted into the thigh. He measured kidney function using a connection between the kidney and the skin. His first patient died 2 days later as the graft was incompatible with the recipient's blood group and was rejected.[2]

It was not until June 17, 1950, when a successful transplant could be performed on Ruth Tucker, a 44-year-old woman with polycystic kidney disease, at Little Company of Mary Hospital in Evergreen Park, Illinois. Although the donated kidney was rejected ten months later because no immunosuppressive therapy was available at the timethe development of effective antirejection drugs was years awaythe intervening time gave Tucker's remaining kidney time to recover and she lived another five years.[3]

The first kidney transplants between living patients were undertaken in 1952 at the Necker hospital in Paris by Jean Hamburger although the kidney failed after 3 weeks of good function [4] and later in 1954 in Boston. The Boston transplantation, performed on December 23, 1954, at Brigham Hospital was performed by Joseph Murray, J. Hartwell Harrison, John P. Merrill and others. The procedure was done between identical twins Ronald and Richard Herrick to eliminate any problems of an immune reaction. For this and later work, Dr. Murray received the Nobel Prize for Medicine in 1990. The recipient, Richard Herrick, died eight years after the transplantation.[5]

The first kidney transplantation in the United Kingdom did not occur until 1960, when Michael Woodruff performed one between identical twins in Edinburgh.[6] Until the routine use of medications to prevent and treat acute rejection, introduced in 1964, deceased donor transplantation was not performed. The kidney was the easiest organ to transplant: tissue typing was simple, the organ was relatively easy to remove and implant, live donors could be used without difficulty, and in the event of failure, kidney dialysis was available from the 1940s. Tissue typing was essential to the success: early attempts in the 1950s on sufferers from Bright's disease had been very unsuccessful.

The major barrier to organ transplantation between genetically non-identical patients lay in the recipient's immune system, which would treat a transplanted kidney as a "non-self" and immediately or chronically reject it. Thus, having medications to suppress the immune system was essential. However, suppressing an individual's immune system places that individual at greater risk of infection and cancer (particularly skin cancer and lymphoma), in addition to the side effects of the medications.

The basis for most immunosuppressive regimens is prednisolone, a corticosteroid. Prednisolone suppresses the immune system, but its long-term use at high doses causes a multitude of side effects, including glucose intolerance and diabetes, weight gain, osteoporosis, muscle weakness, hypercholesterolemia, and cataract formation. Prednisolone alone is usually inadequate to prevent rejection of a transplanted kidney. Thus other, non-steroid immunosuppressive agents are needed, which also allow lower doses of prednisolone.

The indication for kidney transplantation is end-stage renal disease (ESRD), regardless of the primary cause. This is defined as a glomerular filtration rate <15ml/min/1.73 sq.m. Common diseases leading to ESRD include malignant hypertension, infections, diabetes mellitus, and focal segmental glomerulosclerosis; genetic causes include polycystic kidney disease, a number of inborn errors of metabolism, and autoimmune conditions such as lupus. Diabetes is the most common cause of kidney transplantation, accounting for approximately 25% of those in the US. The majority of renal transplant recipients are on dialysis (peritoneal dialysis or hemofiltration) at the time of transplantation. However, individuals with chronic renal failure who have a living donor available may undergo pre-emptive transplantation before dialysis is needed.

Contraindications include both cardiac and pulmonary insufficiency, as well as hepatic disease. Concurrent tobacco use and morbid obesity are also among the indicators putting a patient at a higher risk for surgical complications.

Kidney transplant requirements vary from program to program and country to country. Many programs place limits on age (e.g. the person must be under a certain age to enter the waiting list) and require that one must be in good health (aside from the kidney disease). Significant cardiovascular disease, incurable terminal infectious diseases and cancer are often transplant exclusion criteria. In addition, candidates are typically screened to determine if they will be compliant with their medications, which is essential for survival of the transplant. People with mental illness and/or significant on-going substance abuse issues may be excluded.

HIV was at one point considered to be a complete contraindication to transplantation. There was fear that immunosuppressing someone with a depleted immune system would result in the progression of the disease. However, some research seem to suggest that immunosuppressive drugs and antiretrovirals may work synergistically to help both HIV viral loads/CD4 cell counts and prevent active rejection.

Since medication to prevent rejection is so effective, donors do not need to be similar to their recipient. Most donated kidneys come from deceased donors; however, the utilization of living donors in the United States is on the rise. In 2006, 47% of donated kidneys were from living donors.[7] This varies by country: for example, only 3% of kidneys transplanted during 2006 in Spain came from living donors.[8]

Approximately one in three donations in the US, UK, and Israel is now from a live donor.[9][10][11] Potential donors are carefully evaluated on medical and psychological grounds. This ensures that the donor is fit for surgery and has no disease which brings undue risk or likelihood of a poor outcome for either the donor or recipient. The psychological assessment is to ensure the donor gives informed consent and is not coerced. In countries where paying for organs is illegal, the authorities may also seek to ensure that a donation has not resulted from a financial transaction.

The relationship the donor has to the recipient has evolved over the years. In the 1950s, the first successful living donor transplants were between identical twins. In the 1960s1970s, live donors were genetically related to the recipient. However, during the 1980s1990s, the donor pool was expanded further to emotionally related individuals (spouses, friends). Now the elasticity of the donor relationship has been stretched to include acquaintances and even strangers ("altruistic donors"). In 2009, Minneapolis transplant recipient Chris Strouth received a kidney from a donor who connected with him on Twitter, which is believed to be the first such transplant arranged entirely through social networking.[12][13]

The acceptance of altruistic donors has enabled chains of transplants to form. Kidney chains are initiated when an altruistic donor donates a kidney to a patient who has a willing but incompatible donor. This incompatible donor then "pays it forward" and passes on the generosity to another recipient who also had a willing but incompatible donor. Michael Rees from the University of Toledo developed the concept of open-ended chains.[14] This was a variation of a concept developed at Johns Hopkins University.[15] On July 30, 2008, an altruistic donor kidney was shipped via commercial airline from Cornell to the University of California, Los Angeles, thus triggering a chain of transplants.[16] The shipment of living donor kidneys, computer-matching software algorithms, and cooperation between transplant centers has enabled long-elaborate chains to be formed.[17]

In carefully screened kidney donors, survival and the risk of end-stage renal disease appear to be similar to those in the general population.[18] However, women who have donated a kidney have a higher risk of gestational hypertension and preeclampsia than matched nondonors with similar indicators of baseline health.[19] Traditionally, the donor procedure has been through a single incision of 47 inches (1018cm), but live donation is being increasingly performed by laparoscopic surgery. This reduces pain and accelerates recovery for the donor. Operative time and complications decreased significantly after a surgeon performed 150 cases. Live donor kidney grafts have higher long-term success rates than those from deceased donors.[20] Since the increase in the use of laparoscopic surgery, the number of live donors has increased. Any advance which leads to a decrease in pain and scarring and swifter recovery has the potential to boost donor numbers. In January 2009, the first all-robotic kidney transplant was performed at Saint Barnabas Medical Center through a two-inch incision. In the following six months, the same team performed eight more robotic-assisted transplants.[21]

In 2004 the FDA approved the Cedars-Sinai High Dose IVIG therapy which reduces the need for the living donor to be the same blood type (ABO compatible) or even a tissue match.[22][23] The therapy reduced the incidence of the recipient's immune system rejecting the donated kidney in highly sensitized patients.[23]

In 2009 at the Johns Hopkins Medical Center, a healthy kidney was removed through the donor's vagina. Vaginal donations promise to speed recovery and reduce scarring.[24] The first donor was chosen as she had previously had a hysterectomy.[25] The extraction was performed using natural orifice transluminal endoscopic surgery, where an endoscope is inserted through an orifice, then through an internal incision, so that there is no external scar. The recent advance of single port laparoscopy requiring only one entry point at the navel is another advance with potential for more frequent use.

In the developing world some people sell their organs illegally. Such people are often in grave poverty[26] or are exploited by salespersons. The people who travel to make use of these kidneys are often known as "transplant tourists." This practice is opposed by a variety of human rights groups, including Organs Watch, a group established by medical anthropologists, which was instrumental in exposing illegal international organ selling rings. These patients may have increased complications owing to poor infection control and lower medical and surgical standards. One surgeon has said that organ trade could be legalized in the UK to prevent such tourism, but this is not seen by the National Kidney Research Fund as the answer to a deficit in donors.[27]

In the illegal black market the donors may not get sufficient after-operation care,[28] the price of a kidney may be above $160,000,[29] middlemen take most of the money, the operation is more dangerous to both the donor and receiver, and the buyer often gets hepatitis or HIV.[30] In legal markets of Iran the price of a kidney is $2,000 to $4,000.[30][31]

An article by Gary Becker and Julio Elias on "Introducing Incentives in the market for Live and Cadaveric Organ Donations"[32] said that a free market could help solve the problem of a scarcity in organ transplants. Their economic modeling was able to estimate the price tag for human kidneys ($15,000) and human livers ($32,000).

Now monetary compensation for organ donors is being legalized in Australia and Singapore too. Kidney disease organizations in both countries have expressed their support.[33][34]

Deceased donors can be divided in two groups:

Although brain-dead (or "beating heart") donors are considered dead, the donor's heart continues to pump and maintain the circulation. This makes it possible for surgeons to start operating while the organs are still being perfused (supplied blood). During the operation, the aorta will be cannulated, after which the donor's blood will be replaced by an ice-cold storage solution, such as UW (Viaspan), HTK, or Perfadex. Depending on which organs are transplanted, more than one solution may be used simultaneously. Due to the temperature of the solution, and since large amounts of cold NaCl-solution are poured over the organs for a rapid cooling, the heart will stop pumping.

"Donation after Cardiac Death" donors are patients who do not meet the brain-dead criteria but, due to the unlikely chance of recovery, have elected via a living will or through family to have support withdrawn. In this procedure, treatment is discontinued (mechanical ventilation is shut off). After a time of death has been pronounced, the patient is rushed to the operating room where the organs are recovered. Storage solution is flushed through the organs. Since the blood is no longer being circulated, coagulation must be prevented with large amounts of anti-coagulation agents such as heparin. Several ethical and procedural guidelines must be followed; most importantly, the organ recovery team should not participate in the patient's care in any manner until after death has been declared.

In general, the donor and recipient should be ABO blood group and crossmatch (HLA antigen) compatible. If a potential living donor is incompatible with their recipient, the donor could be exchange for a compatible kidney. Kidney exchange, also known as "kidney paired donation" or "chains" had recently gained popularity over the past few years.

In an effort to reduce the risk of rejection during incompatible transplantation, ABO-incompatible and densensitization protocols utilizing intravenous immunoglobulin (IVIG) have been developed, with the aim to reduce ABO and HLA antibodies that the recipient may have to the donor.

In the 1980s, experimental protocols were developed for ABO-incompatible transplants using increased immunosuppression and plasmapheresis. Through the 1990s these techniques were improved and an important study of long-term outcomes in Japan was published ([1]). Now, a number of programs around the world are routinely performing ABO-incompatible transplants.[35]

The level of sensitization to donor HLA antigens is determined by performing a panel reactive antibody test on the potential recipient. In the United States, up to 17% of all deceased donor kidney transplants have no HLA mismatch. However, HLA matching is a relatively minor predictor of transplant outcomes. In fact, living non-related donors are now almost as common as living (genetically)-related donors.

In most cases the barely functioning existing kidneys are not removed, as this has been shown to increase the rates of surgical morbidities. Therefore, the kidney is usually placed in a location different from the original kidney, often in the iliac fossa, so it is often necessary to use a different blood supply:

There is disagreement in surgical textbooks regarding which side of the recipients pelvis to use in receiving the transplant. Campbell's Urology (2002) recommends placing the donor kidney in the recipients contralateral side (i.e. a left sided kidney would be transplanted in the recipient's right side) to ensure the renal pelvis and ureter are anterior in the event that future surgeries are required. In an instance where there is doubt over whether there is enough space in the recipients pelvis for the donor's kidney the textbook recommends using the right side because the right side has a wider choice of arteries and veins for reconstruction. Smith's Urology (2004) states that either side of the recipient's pelvis is acceptable, however the right vessels are more horizontal with respect to each other and therefore easier to use in the anastomoses. It is unclear what is meant by the words more horizontal. Glen's Urological Surgery (2004) recommends putting the kidney in the contralateral side in all circumstances. No reason is explicitly put forth; however, one can assume the rationale is similar to that of Campbell'sto ensure that the renal pelvis and ureter are most anterior in the event that future surgical correction becomes necessary.

Occasionally, the kidney is transplanted together with the pancreas. University of Minnesota surgeons Richard Lillehei and William Kelly perform the first successful simultaneous pancreas-kidney transplant in the world in 1966.[36] This is done in patients with diabetes mellitus type 1, in whom the diabetes is due to destruction of the beta cells of the pancreas and in whom the diabetes has caused renal failure (diabetic nephropathy). This is almost always a deceased donor transplant. Only a few living donor (partial) pancreas transplants have been done. For individuals with diabetes and renal failure, the advantages of earlier transplant from a living donor (if available) are far superior to the risks of continued dialysis until a combined kidney and pancreas are available from a deceased donor.[citation needed] A patient can either receive a living kidney followed by a donor pancreas at a later date (PAK, or pancreas-after-kidney) or a combined kidney-pancreas from a donor (SKP, simultaneous kidney-pancreas).

Transplanting just the islet cells from the pancreas is still in the experimental stage, but shows promise. This involves taking a deceased donor pancreas, breaking it down, and extracting the islet cells that make insulin. The cells are then injected through a catheter into the recipient and they generally lodge in the liver. The recipient still needs to take immunosuppressants to avoid rejection, but no surgery is required. Most people need two or three such injections, and many are not completely insulin-free.

The transplant surgery takes about three hours.[37] The donor kidney will be placed in the lower abdomen and its blood vessels connected to arteries and veins in the recipient's body. When this is complete, blood will be allowed to flow through the kidney again. The final step is connecting the ureter from the donor kidney to the bladder. In most cases, the kidney will soon start producing urine.

Depending on its quality, the new kidney usually begins functioning immediately. Living donor kidneys normally require 35 days to reach normal functioning levels, while cadaveric donations stretch that interval to 715 days. Hospital stay is typically for 47 days. If complications arise, additional medications (diuretics) may be administered to help the kidney produce urine.

Immunosuppressant drugs are used to suppress the immune system from rejecting the donor kidney. These medicines must be taken for the rest of the recipient's life. The most common medication regimen today is a mixture of tacrolimus, mycophenolate, and prednisone. Some recipients may instead take ciclosporin, sirolimus, or azathioprine. Ciclosporin, considered a breakthrough immunosuppressive when first discovered in the 1980s, ironically causes nephrotoxicity and can result in iatrogenic damage to the newly transplanted kidney. Blood levels must be monitored closely and if the recipient seems to have declining renal function or proteinuria, a biopsy may be necessary to determine whether this is due to rejection [38][39] or ciclosporin intoxication .

Kidney transplant recipients are discouraged from consuming grapefruit, pomegranate and green tea products. These food products are known to interact with the transplant medications, specifically tacrolimus, cyclosporin and sirolimus; the blood levels of these drugs may be increased, potentially leading to an overdose.[40]

Acute rejection occurs in 1025% of people after transplant during the first 60 days.[citation needed] Rejection does not necessarily mean loss of the organ, but it may necessitate additional treatment and medication adjustments.[41]

Problems after a transplant may include: Post operative complication, bleeding, infection, vascular thrombosis and urinary complications

A patient's age and health condition before transplantation affect the risk of complications. Different transplant centers have different success at managing complications and therefore, complication rates are different from center to center.

The average lifetime for a donated kidney is ten to fifteen years. When a transplant fails, a patient may opt for a second transplant, and may have to return to dialysis for some intermediary time.

Infections due to the immunosuppressant drugs used in people with kidney transplants most commonly occur in mucocutaneous areas (41%), the urinary tract (17%) and the respiratory tract (14%).[43] The most common infective agents are bacterial (46%), viral (41%), fungal (13%), and protozoan (1%).[43] Of the viral illnesses, the most common agents are human cytomegalovirus (31.5%), herpes simplex (23.4%), and herpes zoster (23.4%).[43] Infection is the cause of death in about one third of people with renal transplants, and pneumonias account for 50% of the patient deaths from infection.[43]

Kidney transplantation is a life-extending procedure.[44] The typical patient will live 10 to 15 years longer with a kidney transplant than if kept on dialysis.[45] The increase in longevity is greater for younger patients, but even 75-year-old recipients (the oldest group for which there is data) gain an average four more years of life. People generally have more energy, a less restricted diet, and fewer complications with a kidney transplant than if they stay on conventional dialysis.

Some studies seem to suggest that the longer a patient is on dialysis before the transplant, the less time the kidney will last. It is not clear why this occurs, but it underscores the need for rapid referral to a transplant program. Ideally, a kidney transplant should be preemptive, i.e., take place before the patient begins dialysis. The reason why kidneys fail over time after transplantation has been elucidated in recent years. Apart from recurrence of the original kidney disease, also rejection (mainly antibody-mediated rejection) and progressive scarring (multifactorial) play a decisive role.[46] Avoiding rejection by strict medication adherence is of utmost importance to avoid failure of the kidney transplant.

At least four professional athletes have made a comeback to their sport after receiving a transplant: New Zealand rugby union player Jonah Lomu, German-Croatian Soccer Player Ivan Klasni, and NBA basketballers Sean Elliott and Alonzo Mourning.[citation needed]

In addition to nationality, transplantation rates differ based on race, sex, and income. A study done with patients beginning long-term dialysis showed that the sociodemographic barriers to renal transplantation present themselves even before patients are on the transplant list.[53] For example, different groups express definite interest and complete pretransplant workup at different rates. Previous efforts to create fair transplantation policies had focused on patients currently on the transplantation waiting list.

Transplant recipients must take immunosuppressive anti-rejection drugs for as long as the transplanted kidney functions. For the routine immunosuppressives Prograf, Cellcept, and prednisone, these drugs cost US$1,500 per month. In 1999 the United States Congress passed a law that restricts Medicare from paying for more than three years for these drugs, unless the patient is otherwise Medicare-eligible. Transplant programs may not transplant a patient unless the patient has a reasonable plan to pay for medication after the Medicare expires; however, patients are almost never turned down for financial reasons alone. Half of end-stage renal disease patients only have Medicare coverage.

In March 2009 a bill was introduced in the U.S. Senate, 565 and in the House, H.R. 1458 that will extend Medicare coverage of the drugs for as long as the patient has a functioning transplant. This means that patients who have lost their jobs and insurance will not also lose their kidney and be forced back on dialysis. Dialysis is currently using up $17 billion yearly of Medicare funds and total care of these patients amounts to over 10% of the entire Medicare budget.

The United Network for Organ Sharing, which oversees the organ transplants in the United States, allows transplant candidates to register at two or more transplant centers, a practice known as "multiple listing."[54] The practice has been shown to be effective in mitigating the dramatic geographic disparity in the waiting time for organ transplants,[55] particularly for patients residing in high-demand regions such as Boston.[56] The practice of multiple-listing has also been endorsed by medical practitioners.[57][58]

View post:
Kidney transplantation - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Read More...

Gene therapy – PBS

October 24th, 2015 3:44 pm

A treatment for Cystic Fibrosis. A cure for AIDS. The end of cancer. That's what the newspapers promised us in the early 1990's. Gene therapy was the answer to what ailed us. Scientists had at last learned how to insert healthy genes into unhealthy people. And those healthy genes would either replace the bad genes causing diseases like CF, sickle-cell anemia and hemophilia or stimulate the body's own immune system to rid itself of HIV and some forms of cancer. A decade later, none of these treatments have come to fruition and research into gene therapy has become politically unpopular, making clinical trials hard to approve and research dollars hard to come by. But some researchers who are taking a different approach to gene therapy could be on the road to more success than ever before. - - - - - - - - - - - -

Early Promise

Almost as soon as Watson and Crick unwound the double helix in the 1950's, researchers began considering the possibility- and ethics- of gene therapy. The goals were lofty- to fix inherited genetic diseases such as Cystic Fibrosis and hemophilia forever.

Gene therapists planned to isolate the relevant gene in question, prepare good copies of that gene, then deliver them to patients' cells. The hope was that the treated cells would give rise to new generations of healthy cells for the rest of the patient's life. The concept was elegant, but would require decades of research to locate the genes that cause illnesses.

By 1990, it was working in the lab. By inserting healthy genes into cells from CF patients, scientists were able to transmogrify the sick cells as if by magic into healthy cells.

That same year, four-year-old Ashanti DeSilva became the first person in history to receive gene therapy. Dr. W. French Anderson of the National Heart, Lung and Blood Institute and Dr. Michael Blaese and Dr. Kenneth Culver, both of the National Cancer Institute, performed the historic and controversial experiment.

DeSilva suffered from a rare immune disorder known as ADA deficiency that made her vulnerable to even the mildest infections. A single genetic defect- like a typo in a novel- left DeSilva unable to produce an important enzyme. Without that enzyme, DeSilva was likely to die a premature death.

Anderson, Blaese and Culver drew the girl's blood and treated her defective white blood cells with the gene she lacked. The altered cells were then injected back into the girl, where- the scientists hoped- they would produce the enzyme she needed as well as produce future generations of normal cells.

Though the treatment proved safe, its efficacy is still in question. The treated cells did produce the enzyme, but failed to give rise to healthy new cells. DeSilva, who is today relatively healthy, still receives periodic gene therapy to maintain the necessary levels of the enzyme in her blood. She also takes doses of the enzyme itself, in the form of a drug called PEG-ADA, which makes it difficult to tell how well the gene therapy would have worked alone.

"It was a very logical approach," says Dr. Jeffrey Isner, Chief of Vascular Medicine and Cardiovascular Research at St. Elizabeth's Medical Center in Boston as well as Professor of Medicine at Tufts University School of Medicine. "But in most cases the strategy failed, because the vectors we have today are not ready for prime time." - - - - - - - - - - - - 4 pages: | 1 | 2 | 3 | 4 |

Photo: Dr. W. French Anderson

See the article here:
Gene therapy - PBS

Read More...

Breast Augmentation with Autologous Fat and Stem Cells …

October 24th, 2015 3:43 pm

At a Glance

Schedule appointment or Skype information

Breast augmentation with stem cell-enriched autologous fat (cell-assisted lipotransfer (CAL)), enables breast augmentation to be carried out without using silicone or other artificial fillers, without the use of scalpels or general anesthesia, leaving no scars and with no negative effects on the natural breast function.

This procedure is suitable for women who always wanted to have larger breasts and also for those whose original breast volume has decreased, e.g., by breastfeeding or weight loss. Augmentation of around one half up to two cup sizes is usually possible with one intervention.

After an in-depth advice and medical consultation, you can schedule an appointment for surgery at a date of your choice.

Breast augmentation is carried out on an outpatient basis using local anesthesia in our specially-equipped operating rooms. The procedure takes approx. 3 to 4 hours.

We use liposuction to harvest the autologous fat required for obtaining stem cells and the actual breast augmentation. Liposculpture is a special form of liposuction, whereby we extract fat from the bodys fat depots by suction. This method is done by hand and is gentle on the tissue. We never use suction machines or scalpels.

Thin microcannulas with a diameter of 1.0 to 2.5 millimeters are used for liposuction or alternatively, conventional regular cannulas with a diameter of 3.0 millimeters upwards. Experience has shown that microcannulas have to be used on very slim women to harvest sufficient fat.

A part of your autologous fat is used to obtain your own bodys stem cells, which is processed with the remaining body fat in clean room conditions, and injected into your breasts.

Using this stem cell-enriched fat, a considerably longer-lasting result can be achieved than with other methods of autologous fat transfer. In the long term, normally a large part of the volume introduced is retained, which is why one intervention usually suffices.

Aftercare is relatively straightforward: You must wear a bandage overnight and wear compression garments afterwards. If regular cannulas were used, you need to wear the compression garments for 6 to 8 weeks; if liposuction was carried out with microcannulas, usually they have to be worn for 1 week. A sports bra should be worn for approx. 4 weeks.

You usually should be able to go back to work 1 to 2 days after having breast augmentation with stem cell-enriched autologous fat. It is important that you do not lift anything heavy during the first few weeks after surgery. Wear comfortable loose clothing over the compression garments to cover up your little secret.

Can You Drink Beauty?

Perfect Skin by DDr.Heinrich Beauty Drink

The type of sport and your individual healing process determine when you will be able to begin sports again. We will monitor your health during the healing process and give you recommendations tailored to your needs.

The positive results of breast augmentation with autologous stem cells can be seen by their natural appearance and youthful firmness. Since the additional volume consists exclusively of your bodys own material, the augmented breast feels absolutely real and looks natural in any posture, whether you are at rest or moving. Additionally, the local rejuvenating effect of the stem cells often gives the breasts a younger, firmer and more toned appearance.

Breast augmentation of approx. one half up to two cup sizes can be achieved with one intervention. Augmentations of around one cup size are typical. The punctures on the breast made by injection needles almost always heal with scars invisible to the naked eye, just as when blood samples are taken.

After breast augmentation with stem cell-enriched autologous fat, normally a large part of the new breast volume is retained for years. Refreshments are therefore mostly unnecessary.

See the article here:
Breast Augmentation with Autologous Fat and Stem Cells ...

Read More...

Diabetes and Endocrinology | Diabetes Center St Louis …

October 24th, 2015 12:45 pm

Barnes-Jewish & Washington University Diabetes Center The Washington University Diabetes Center at Barnes-Jewish Hospital is designed to offer an easier way to a better life. The Diabetes Center is an American Diabetes Association nationally recognized quality education program.

The comprehensive Diabetes Center is unique in the region, offering the latest in treatment and technology for patients with diabetes. This treatment includes convenient access to essential services including:

Patients have access to leading-edge treatment for even the most complicated cases. With a comprehensive, one-stop location for diabetes care, patients are better able to manage their symptoms from diabetes, and possibly avoid potential complications from uncontrolled blood sugar levels.

Through the Diabetes Center, patients with diabetes throughout the Midwest can access the latest advancements in diabetes treatment and a comprehensive range of services in one convenient setting. The Diabetes Center's focus is on making treatment fit your life so your diabetes is easier for you to manage.

With the multi-specialty team of the Diabetes Center working together, patients enjoy an improved quality and depth of diabetes-related medical treatment. The Diabetes Center, located on the 13th floor of the Center for Advanced Medicine at Barnes-Jewish Hospital, serves as a meaningful resource for patients, their families and their referring physicians. In partnership with referring physicians, the Diabetes Center team of specialists help patients manage complex cases or complications to those newly diagnosed.

The well-planned, comfortable Diabetes Center includes private and group education rooms, as well as a foot care area with a specially designed chair for exams and treatment. We have even designed wider doorways and larger exam tables to ensure your comfort. Our team takes the time to thoroughly evaluate you and provide the individual attention you deserve.

As you know, diabetes is a complex disease. It is progressive and can affect every part of your body in some way. At the Diabetes Center, you'll benefit from physicians and staff who specialize in diabetes and understand its many facets. The Center will make it easier to manage your disease.

The Diabetes Center enables specialists to work closely together sharing information and collaborating so all your medical and medication needs are addressed. The bottom line is you receive more effective diabetes management.

The Diabetes Center's team includes top-ranked endocrinologists (diabetes specialists) and disease-related specialists, including:

In addition, the team includes diabetes nurse practitioners, certified diabetes nurse educators, registered dietitians and a certified foot nurse. Our medical assistants are all trained to provide a high level of support to our diabetes patients. The team works closely with you and your primary care physician to create an individualized treatment plan. Ultimately, the team is committed to empower you to control your diabetes.

Read more here:
Diabetes and Endocrinology | Diabetes Center St Louis ...

Read More...

Texas Gov. Rick Perry Received Experimental Stem Cell …

October 23rd, 2015 7:50 pm

Texas Gov. Rick Perry, a potential presidential candidate, underwent spinal fusion surgery in early July that included an injection of his own stem cells, a therapy that is unapproved by the FDA and costs tens of thousands of dollars.

While the Texas governor supports adult stem cell research, he is an opponent of embryonic stem cell research, a position held by the social conservative base.

As first reported by the Texas Tribune, Perry's surgery included "the innovative use of his own adult stem cells" and any cost not covered by health insurance was paid for by Perry, according to his spokesman Mark Miner.

The stem cell treatment was the doctor's first attempt at the surgery ever, and the lab responsible for culturing Perry's stem cells is a branch of a South Korean company that has become known for commercialized dog cloning, "regenerative" beauty products, and accusations of conducting "stem cell tourism."

According to the Texas Tribune, Dr. Stanley Jones, a Houston orthopedic surgeon and personal friend of Perry, removed two teaspoons of fatty tissue from the governor's hip and placed it in a culture, waiting several weeks before the stem cells expanded. Jones later injected the stem cells into the governor's spine and into his blood stream to help speed up the healing process.

On the day of his surgery, Perry tweeted, "Little procedure went as advertised. Blessed to be married to the world's best nurse. Thanks for all the prayers!!"

Perry has been a strong proponent of adult stem cell research, even urging the Texas Medical Board to consider enhancing the state's position on adult stem cell research. In his 2009 State of the State address, Perry called for greater investment in the adult stem cell industry.

"Let's get Texas in on the ground floor and invest in adult stem cell research, the one area of that field that is actually proven to expedite cures," Perry said. "Expertise in this emerging and increasingly promising field will not only bring healing to the suffering and create jobs for Texans, it will also establish an appropriate firewall protecting the unborn from exploitation."

However, Perry opposes any form of embryonic stem cell research, a position that resonates with the social conservatives in the GOP. Perry's 2010 gubernatorial campaign website touts his support for banning embryonic stem cell research, a position held by a majority of the social conservative base.

"Gov. Perry supports a ban on human cloning and has vowed to veto any legislation that provides state dollars for embryonic stem cell research," the website reads. "He has been a strong advocate of utilizing adult stem cells in their place. Adult stem cell research can provide much-needed solutions for Texans suffering from various tissue and organ disorders while protecting the unborn from exploitation. They are also proven more effective in research than embryonic stem cells."

The Family Research Council, which opposes embryonic stem cell research, said Perry's use of adult stem cell therapy will reinforce the success of adult stem cells and will show embryonic stem cell therapy is not needed.

"We're actually very pleased that Gov. Perry would make public the fact that he used his own adult stem cells as part of this surgery to assist the healing process," Dr. David Prentice, senior fellow for life sciences at the Family Research Council, told ABC News. "People see that you don't need or want embryonic stem cells. You want, instead, those cells that work. Adult stem cells are ethical, but they're successful and they're working for thousands of patients right now, including, apparently, Gov. Perry."

But the Genetics Policy Institute, a public interest organization that supports all forms of stem cell research, warned that Perry should use his experimental therapy as an educational moment about consumer fraud in the stem cell field.

"As a public figure that availed himself of an experimental treatment, it behooves him to release to the public enough details about it to know that the treatment was legitimate," Bernard Siegel, executive director of the Genetics Policy Institute, told ABC News. "He needs to be aware of the consumer fraud that's out there and people who are desperate patients being lured to clinics, many of them abroad, that are selling snake oil and using the label stem cell to bring people in."

Last week, a federal judge threw out a lawsuit challenging the use of federal funding for embryonic stem cell research.

See the original post:
Texas Gov. Rick Perry Received Experimental Stem Cell ...

Read More...

Cancer stem cell – Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

October 23rd, 2015 7:49 pm

Cancer stem cells (CSCs) are cancer cells (found within tumors or hematological cancers) that possess characteristics associated with normal stem cells, specifically the ability to give rise to all cell types found in a particular cancer sample. CSCs are therefore tumorigenic (tumor-forming), perhaps in contrast to other non-tumorigenic cancer cells. CSCs may generate tumors through the stem cell processes of self-renewal and differentiation into multiple cell types. Such cells are hypothesized to persist in tumors as a distinct population and cause relapse and metastasis by giving rise to new tumors. Therefore, development of specific therapies targeted at CSCs holds hope for improvement of survival and quality of life of cancer patients, especially for patients with metastatic disease.

Existing cancer treatments have mostly been developed based on animal models, where therapies able to promote tumor shrinkage were deemed effective. However, animals do not provide a complete model of human disease. In particular, in mice, whose life spans do not exceed two years, tumor relapse is difficult to study.

The efficacy of cancer treatments is, in the initial stages of testing, often measured by the ablation fraction of tumor mass (fractional kill). As CSCs form a small proportion of the tumor, this may not necessarily select for drugs that act specifically on the stem cells. The theory suggests that conventional chemotherapies kill differentiated or differentiating cells, which form the bulk of the tumor but do not generate new cells. A population of CSCs, which gave rise to it, could remain untouched and cause relapse.

Cancer stem cells were first identified by John Dick in acute myeloid leukemia in the late 1990s. Since the early 2000s they have been an intense focus of cancer research[1]

In different tumor subtypes, cells within the tumor population exhibit functional heterogeneity, and tumors are formed from cells with various proliferative and differentiate capacities.[2] This functional tumour heterogeneity among cancer cells has led to the creation of at least two models, which have been put forward to account for heterogeneity and differences in tumor-regenerative capacity: the cancer stem cell (CSC) and clonal evolution models[3]

The cancer stem cell model refers to a subset of tumor cells that have the ability to self-renew and are able to generate the diverse tumor cells.[3] These cells have been termed cancer stem cells to reflect their stem-like properties. One implication of the CSC model and the existence of CSCs is that the tumor population is hierarchically arranged with CSCs lying at the apex of the hierarchy[4] (Fig. 3).

The clonal evolution model postulates that mutant tumor cells with a growth advantage are selected and expanded. Cells in the dominant population have a similar potential for initiating tumor growth[5] (Fig. 4).

[6] These two models are not mutually exclusive, as CSCs themselves undergo clonal evolution. Thus, the secondary more dominant CSCs may emerge, if a mutation confers more aggressive properties[7] (Fig. 5).

The existence of CSCs is a subject of debate within medical research, because many studies have not been successful in discovering the similarities and differences between normal tissue stem cells and cancer (stem) cells.[8] Cancer cells must be capable of continuous proliferation and self-renewal in order to retain the many mutations required for carcinogenesis, and to sustain the growth of a tumor since differentiated cells (constrained by the Hayflick Limit[9]) cannot divide indefinitely. However, it is debated whether such cells represent a minority. If most cells of the tumor are endowed with stem cell properties, there is no incentive to focus on a specific subpopulation. There is also debate on the cell of origin of CSCs - whether they originate from normal stem cells that have lost the ability to regulate proliferation, or from more differentiated population of progenitor cells that have acquired abilities to self-renew (which is related to the issue of stem cell plasticity).

The first conclusive evidence for CSCs was published in 1997 in Nature Medicine. Bonnet and Dick[10] isolated a subpopulation of leukaemic cells that expressed a specific surface marker CD34, but lacked the CD38 marker. The authors established that the CD34+/CD38 subpopulation is capable of initiating tumors in NOD/SCID mice that are histologically similar to the donor. The first evidence of a solid tumor cancer stem-like cell followed in 2002 with the discovery of a clonogenic, sphere-forming cell isolated and characterized from human brain gliomas [Human cortical glial tumors contain neural stem-like cells expressing astroglial and neuronal markers in vitro.[11]

In cancer research experiments, tumor cells are sometimes injected into an experimental animal to establish a tumor. Disease progression is then followed in time and novel drugs can be tested for their ability to inhibit it. However, efficient tumor formation requires thousands or tens of thousands of cells to be introduced. Classically, this has been explained by poor methodology (i.e. the tumor cells lose their viability during transfer) or the critical importance of the microenvironment, the particular biochemical surroundings of the injected cells. Supporters of the CSC paradigm argue that only a small fraction of the injected cells, the CSCs, have the potential to generate a tumor. In human acute myeloid leukemia the frequency of these cells is less than 1 in 10,000.[10]

Further evidence comes from histology, the study of the tissue structure of tumors. Many tumors are very heterogeneous and contain multiple cell types native to the host organ. Heterogeneity is commonly retained by tumor metastases. This implies that the cell that produced them had the capacity to generate multiple cell types. In other words, it possessed multidifferentiative potential, a classical hallmark of stem cells.[10]

The existence of leukaemic stem cells prompted further research into other types of cancer. CSCs have recently been identified in several solid tumors, including cancers of the:

Once the pathways to cancer are hypothesized, it is possible to develop predictive mathematical biology models,[29] e.g., based on the cell compartment method. For instance, the growths of the abnormal cells from their normal counterparts can be denoted with specific mutation probabilities. Such a model has been employed to predict that repeated insult to mature cells increases the formation of abnormal progeny, and hence the risk of cancer.[30] Considerable work needs to be done, however, before the clinical efficacy of such models[31] is established.

The origin of cancer stem cells is still an area of ongoing research. Several camps have formed within the scientific community regarding the issue, and it is possible that several answers are correct, depending on the tumor type and the phenotype the tumor presents. One important distinction that will often be raised is that the cell of origin for a tumor can not be demonstrated using the cancer stem cell as a model. This is because cancer stem cells are isolated from end-stage tumors. Therefore, describing a cancer stem cell as a cell of origin is often an inaccurate claim, even though a cancer stem cell is capable of initiating new tumor formation.

With that caveat mentioned, various theories define the origin of cancer stem cells. In brief, CSC can be generated as: mutants in developing stem or progenitor cells, mutants in adult stem cells or adult progenitor cells, or mutant differentiated cells that acquire stem-like attributes. These theories often do focus on a tumor's cell of origin and as such must be approached with skepticism.

Some researchers favor the theory that the cancer stem cell is generated by a mutation in stem cell niche populations during development. The logical progression claims that these developing stem populations are mutated and then expand such that the mutation is shared by many of the descendants of the mutated stem cell. These daughter stem cells are then much closer to becoming tumors, and since there are many of them there is more chance of a mutation that can cause cancer.[32]

Another theory associates adult stem cells with the formation of tumors. This is most often associated with tissues with a high rate of cell turnover (such as the skin or gut). In these tissues, it has long been expected that stem cells are responsible for tumor formation. This is a consequence of the frequent cell divisions of these stem cells (compared to most adult stem cells) in conjunction with the extremely long lifespan of adult stem cells. This combination creates the ideal set of circumstances for mutations to accumulate; accumulation of mutations is the primary factor that drives cancer initiation. In spite of the logical backing of the theory, only recently has any evidence appeared showing association represents an actual phenomenon. It is important to bear in mind that due to the heterogeneous nature of evidence it is possible that any individual cancer could come from an alternative origin. Recent evidence supports the idea that cancer stem cells, and cancer, arise from normal stem cells.[33][34]

A third possibility often raised is the potential de-differentiation of mutated cells such that these cells acquire stem cell like characteristics. This is often used as a potential alternative to any specific cell of origin, as it suggests that any cell might become a cancer stem cell.

Another related concept is the concept of tumor hierarchy. This concept claims that a tumor is a heterogeneous population of mutant cells, all of which share some mutations but vary in specific phenotype. In this model, the tumor is made up of several types of stem cells, one optimal to the specific environment and several less successful lines. These secondary lines can become more successful in some environments, allowing the tumor to adapt to its environment, including adaptation to tumor treatment. If this situation is accurate, it has severe repercussions on cancer stem cell specific treatment regime.[35] Within a tumor hierarchy model, it would be extremely difficult to pinpoint the cancer stem cell's origin.

CSC, now reported in most human tumors, are commonly identified and enriched using strategies for identifying normal stem cells that are similar across various studies.[36] The procedures include fluorescence-activated cell sorting (FACS), with antibodies directed at cell-surface markers, and functional approaches including SP analysis (side population assay) or Aldefluor assay.[37] The CSC-enriched population purified by these approaches is then implanted, at various cell doses, in immune-deficient mice to assess its tumor development capacity. This in vivo assay is called limiting dilution assay. The tumor cell subsets that can initiate tumor development at low cell numbers are further tested for self-renewal capacity in serial tumor studies.[38]

CSC can also be identified by efflux of incorporated Hoechst dyes via multidrug resistance (MDR) and ATP-binding cassette (ABC) Transporters.[37]

Another approach which has also been used for identification of cell subsets enriched with CSCs in vitro is sphere-forming assays. Many normal stem cells such as hematopoietics or stem cells from tissues are capable, under special culture conditions, to form three-dimensional spheres, which can differentiate into multiple cell types. As with normal stem cells, the CSCs isolated from brain or prostate tumors also have the ability to form anchorage-independent spheres.[39]

Data over recent years have indicated the existence of CSCs in various solid tumors. For isolating CSCs from solid and hematological tumors, markers specific for normal stem cells of the same organ are commonly used. Nevertheless, a number of cell surface markers have proved useful for isolation of subsets enriched for CSC including CD133 (also known as PROM1), CD44, CD24, EpCAM (epithelial cell adhesion molecule, also known as epithelial specific antigen, ESA), THY1, ATP-binding cassette B5 (ABCB5).,[40] and CD200.

CD133 (prominin 1) is a five-transmembrane domain glycoprotein expressed on CD34+ stem and progenitor cells, in endothelial precursors and fetal neural stem cells. It has been detected using its glycosylated epitope known as AC133.

EpCAM (epithelial cell adhesion molecule, ESA, TROP1) is hemophilic Ca2+-independent cell adhesion molecule expressed on the basolateral surface of most Epithelial cells.

CD90 (THY1) is a glycosylphosphatidylinositol glycoprotein anchored in the plasma membrane and involved in signal transduction. It may also mediate adhesion between thymocytes and thymic stroma.

CD44 (PGP1) is an adhesion molecule that has pleiotropic roles in cell signaling, migration and homing. It has multiple isoforms, including CD44H, which exhibits high affinity for hyaluronate, and CD44V which has metastatic properties.

CD24 (HSA) is a glycosylated glycosylphosphatidylinositol-anchored adhesion molecule, which has co-stimulatory role in B and T cells.

CD200 (OX-2) is a type 1 membrane glycoprotein, which delivers an inhibitory signal to immune cells including T cells, NK cells and macrophages.

ALDH is a ubiquitous aldehyde dehydrogenase family of enzymes, which catalyzes the oxidation of aromatic aldehydes to carboxyl acids. For instance, it has role in conversion of retinol to retinoic acid, which is essential for survival.[41][42]

The first solid malignancy from which CSCs were isolated and identified was breast cancer. Therefore, these CSCs are the most intensely studied. Breast CSCs have been enriched in CD44+CD24/low,[40] SP,[43]ALDH+ subpopulations.[44][45] However, recent evidence indicates that breast CSCs are very phenotypically diverse, and there is evidence that not only CSC marker expression in breast cancer cells is heterogeneous but also there exist many subsets of breast CSC.[46] Last studies provide further support to this point. Both CD44+CD24 and CD44+CD24+ cell populations are tumor initiating cells; however, CSC are most highly enriched using the marker profile CD44+CD49fhiCD133/2hi.[47]

CSCs have been reported in many brain tumors. Stem-like tumor cells have been identified using cell surface markers including CD133,[48]SSEA-1 (stage-specific embryonic antigen-1),[49]EGFR[50] and CD44.[51] However, there is uncertainty about the use of CD133 for identification of brain tumor stem-like cells because tumorigenic cells are found in both CD133+ and CD133 cells in some gliomas, and some CD133+ brain tumor cells may not possess tumor-initiating capacity.[50]

Similarly, CSCs have also been reported in human colon cancer.[52] For their identification, cell surface markers such as CD133,[52] CD44[53] and ABCB5,[54] or functional analysis including clonal analysis [55] or Aldefluor assay were used.[56] Using CD133 as a positive marker for colon CSCs has generated conflicting results. Nevertheless, recent studies indicated that the AC133 epitope, but not the CD133 protein, is specifically expressed in colon CSCs and its expression is lost upon differentiation.[57] In addition, using CD44+ colon cancer cells and additional sub-fractionation of CD44+EpCAM+ cell population with CD166 enhance the success of tumor engraftments.[53]

Multiple CSCs have been reported in prostate,[58]lung and many other organs, including liver, pancreas, kidney or ovary.[41][59] In prostate cancer, the tumor-initiating cells have been identified in CD44+[60] cell subset as CD44+21+,[61] TRA-1-60+CD151+CD166+[62] or ALDH+[63] cell populations. Putative markers for lung CSCs have been reported, including CD133+,[64] ALDH+,[65] CD44+[66] and oncofetal protein 5T4+.[67]

Metastasis is the major cause of tumor lethality in patients. However, not every cell in the tumor has the ability to metastasize. This potential depends on factors that determine growth, angiogenesis, invasion and other basic processes of tumor cells. In the many epithelial tumors, the epithelial-mesenchymal transition (EMT) is considered as a crucial events in the metastatic process.[68] EMT and the reverse transition from mesenchymal to an epithelial phenotype (MET) are involved in embryonic development, which involves disruption of epithelial cell homeostasis and the acquisition of a migratory mesenchymal phenotype.[69] The EMT appears to be controlled by canonical pathways such as WNT and transforming growth factor pathway.[70] The important feature of EMT is the loss of membrane E-cadherin in adherens junctions, where the -catenin may play a significant role. Translocation of -catenin from adherens junctions to the nucleus may lead to a loss of E-cadherin, and subsequently to EMT. There is evidence that nuclear -catenin can directly transcriptionally activate EMT-associated target genes, such as the E-cadherin gene repressor SLUG (also known as SNAI2).[71]

Recent data have supported the concept, that tumor cells undergoing an EMT could be precursors for metastatic cancer cells, or even metastatic CSCs.[72] In the invasive edge of pancreatic carcinoma a subset of CD133+CXCR4+ (receptor for CXCL12 chemokine also known as a SDF1 ligand) cells has been defined. These cells exhibited significantly stronger migratory activity than their counterpart CD133+CXCR4 cells, but both cell subsets showed similar tumor development capacity.[73] Moreover, inhibition of the CXCR4 receptor led to the reduced metastatic potential without altering tumorigenic capacity.[74]

On the other hand, in the breast cancer CD44+CD24/low cells are detectable in metastatic pleural effusions.[40] By contrast, an increased number of CD24+ cells have been identified in distant metastases in patients with breast cancer.[75] Although, there are only few data on mechanisms mediating metastasis in breast cancer, it is possible that CD44+CD24/low cells initially metastasize and in the new site they change their phenotype and undergo limited differentiation.[76] These findings led to new dynamic two-phase expression pattern concept based on the existence of two forms of cancer stem cells - stationary cancer stem cells (SCS) and mobile cancer stem cells (MCS). SCS are embedded in tissue and persist in differentiated areas throughout all tumor progression. The term MCS describes cells that are located at the tumor-host interface. There is an evidence that these cells are derived from SCS through the acquisition of transient EMT [77] (Fig. 7)

The existence of CSCs has several implications in terms of future cancer treatment and therapies. These include disease identification, selective drug targets, prevention of metastasis, and development of new intervention strategies.

Normal somatic stem cells are naturally resistant to chemotherapeutic agents. They produce various pumps (such as MDR[citation needed]) that pump out drugs and DNA repair proteins and they also have a slow rate of cell turnover (chemotherapeutic agents naturally target rapidly replicating cells)[citation needed]. CSCs that develop from normal stem cells may also produce these proteins, which could increase their resistance towards chemotherapeutic agents. The surviving CSCs then repopulate the tumor, causing a relapse.[78] By selectively targeting CSCs, it would be possible to treat patients with aggressive, non-resectable tumors, as well as preventing patients from metastasizing and relapsing.[78] The hypothesis suggests that upon CSC elimination, cancer could regress due to differentiation and/or cell death[citation needed]. What fraction of tumor cells are CSCs and therefore need to be eliminated is not clear yet.[79]

A number of studies have investigated the possibility of identifying specific markers that may distinguish CSCs from the bulk of the tumor (as well as from normal stem cells).[13] Proteomic and genomic signatures of tumors are also being investigated.[80][citation needed]. In 2009, scientists identified one compound, Salinomycin, that selectively reduces the proportion of breast CSCs in mice by more than 100-fold relative to Paclitaxel, a commonly used chemotherapeutic agent.[81] Some types of cancer cells can survive treatment with salinomycin through autophagy,[82] whereby cells use acidic organelles like lysosomes, to degrade and recycle certain types of proteins. The use of autophagy inhibitors can enable killing of cancer stem cells that survive by autophagy.[83]

The cell surface receptor interleukin-3 receptor-alpha (CD123) was shown to be overexpressed on CD34+CD38- leukemic stem cells (LSCs) in acute myelogenous leukemia (AML) but not on normal CD34+CD38- bone marrow cells.[84] Jin et al., then demonstrated that treating AML-engrafted NOD/SCID mice with a CD123-specific monoclonal antibody impaired LSCs homing to the bone marrow and reduced overall AML cell repopulation including the proportion of LSCs in secondary mouse recipients.[85]

The design of new drugs for the treatment of CSCs will likely require an understanding of the cellular mechanisms that regulate cell proliferation. The first advances in this area were made with hematopoietic stem cells (HSCs) and their transformed counterparts in leukemia, the disease for which the origin of CSCs is best understood. It is now becoming increasingly clear that stem cells of many organs share the same cellular pathways as leukemia-derived HSCs.

Additionally, a normal stem cell may be transformed into a cancer stem cell through disregulation of the proliferation and differentiation pathways controlling it or by inducing oncoprotein activity.

The Polycomb group transcriptional repressor Bmi-1 was discovered as a common oncogene activated in lymphoma[86] and later shown to specifically regulate HSCs.[87] The role of Bmi-1 has also been illustrated in neural stem cells.[88] The pathway appears to be active in CSCs of pediatric brain tumors.[89]

The Notch pathway has been known to developmental biologists for decades. Its role in control of stem cell proliferation has now been demonstrated for several cell types including hematopoietic, neural and mammary[90] stem cells. Components of the Notch pathway have been proposed to act as oncogenes in mammary[91] and other tumors.

A particular branch of the Notch signaling pathway that involves the transcription factor Hes3 has been shown to regulate a number of cultured cells with cancer stem cell characteristics obtained from glioblastoma patients.[92]

These developmental pathways are also strongly implicated as stem cell regulators.[93] Both Sonic hedgehog (SHH) and Wnt pathways are commonly hyperactivated in tumors and are required to sustain tumor growth. However, the Gli transcription factors that are regulated by SHH take their name from gliomas, where they are commonly expressed at high levels. A degree of crosstalk exists between the two pathways and their activation commonly goes hand-in-hand.[94] This is a trend rather than a rule. For instance, in colon cancer hedgehog signalling appears to antagonise Wnt.[95]

Sonic hedgehog blockers are available, such as cyclopamine. There is also a new water-soluble cyclopamine that may be more effective in cancer treatment. There is also DMAPT, a water-soluble derivative of parthenolide (induces oxidative stress, inhibits NF-B signaling[96]) for AML (leukemia), and possibly myeloma and prostate cancer. A clinical trial of DMAPT is to start in England in late 2007 or 2008[citation needed]. Finally, the enzyme telomerase may qualify as a study subject in CSC physiology.[97] GRN163L (Imetelstat) was recently started in trials to target myeloma stem cells. If it is possible to eliminate the cancer stem cell, then a potential cure may be achieved if there are no more CSCs to repopulate a cancer.

The monolayer of CSCs grown as spheroids showed better growth rate than the MDA-MB 231 cells, which shows the efficacy of 3D spheroid format of growing CSCs. CD44 show increased expression in spheroids compared to 2D culture of MDA-MB 231. ALDH1 a key marker of breast stem cells was highly expressed in BCSCs and MDA-MB 231 grown in 3D, while being absent in CSCs and MDA-MB 231 cells grown in 2D.

The CSCs grown as spheroids showed better growth rate, which showed the efficacy of 3D spheroid format for CSCs culture. Since the association between BCSCs prevalence and clinical outcome and the evidence presented in this study support key roles of CSCs in breast cancer metastasis and drug resistance, it has been proposed that new therapies must target these cells[98]

Read the rest here:
Cancer stem cell - Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Read More...

Department of Microbiology and Molecular Genetics at the …

October 23rd, 2015 7:47 pm

Whether you're seeking a B.S. or a Ph.D. in Microbiology or Molecular Genetics, you'll find our department has broad research strengths ranging from molecular, structural, and computational biology to cellular and pathogenic microbiology. You will have access to a rich course curriculum and research laboratories where experienced and supportive faculty will guide your research and help you sharpen your scientific communication skills.

Our research addresses fundamental questions in eukaryotic and prokaryotic cell and molecular biology, using the methods of microbiology, genetics, biochemistry, bioinformatics, and structural biology. This work bears directly on crucial health-related problems such as cancer, AIDS, and infectious disease. Outstanding institutional core facilities provide access to the latest research technologies. The highly collaborative culture of the department is fostered by cross-departmental meetings and journal clubs on a variety of interdisciplinary topics, including DNA repair, parasitology and microbial pathogenesis, and by cross-college consortia such as the Vermont Center for Immunobiology and Infectious Disease. Learn More

The collaborative and interdisciplinary nature of our research programs means that a prospective graduate student is offered a wide choice of research opportunities. While all of our students take the same core curriculum, in their second year they choose to specialize in one of four advanced concentration areas. Our alumni have gone on to become university professors, journal editors and senior scientists and executives in the biotechnology industry. UVM is located in Burlington VT, consistently ranked one of the best places to live in the USA. Learn more

Unique opportunities await students majoring in Microbiology or Molecular Genetics at UVM. Our program is small, which permits our faculty to give each student the individual attention necessary to help them succeed. Our lecture and cutting-edge laboratory courses are challenging and provide each student with a strong foundation and the confidence to work at the bench. The flexibility of our curriculum is such that students can get credit for summer internships or for performing research in one of the many labs at UVM. Small classes foster long lasting camaraderie among our students: MMG'ers are quick to support each other, suggest study tips or point out where to find the best pizza. A student in MMG is never a face in the crowd; our students receive one-on-one mentoring and more often than not end up achieving more than they thought they could. Learn more

See the article here:
Department of Microbiology and Molecular Genetics at the ...

Read More...

How Long Will I Live? – Life Expectancy Calculator

October 23rd, 2015 7:47 pm

We have been working to update the interface of the tool and integrate the latest available data into our calculations. Shortly, this version of the calculator will be replaced. The beta version of the updated calculator is available here. Feedback? Fill out this quick survey to let us know. Fill in the following form then click the button labeled "Calculate Life Expectancy". For values which you are unsure of, leave it blank or choose option 'don't know'; For zero values, enter "0", DO NOT leave them blank If you're in a hurry, try our Short life expectancy calculator.

I am year old male female white nonwhite My height is inches (NOTE!!! Only input inches: Eg. 5'8" = 68 inches) My weight is pounds I expect to have less than 10 10 to 11 more than 11 don't know years of education My family's total income for the past 12 months is dollars I expect that for most of my life I will be married not married don't know Compared to other people of the same age and sex as me, I am in the 1st (least fit) 2nd 3rd 4th 5th (fittest) don't know quintile of fitness(refer to Fitness Table) I do not do don't know have at least one first degree relative (parents, sibling, children) who has a history of heart diseases I do not do don't know have at least one first degree relative (parents, sibling, children) who has a history of prostate cancer I do not do don't know have at least one first degree relative (parents, sibling, children) who has a history of breast cancer I do not do don't know have at least one first degree relative (parents, sibling, children) who has a history of colorectal cancer I do not do don't know have at least one first degree relative (parents, sibling, children) who has a history of stomach cancer I do not do don't know have at least one first degree relative (parents, sibling, children) who has a history of lung cancer None One Two or more don't know of my first degree relative (parents, sibling, children) has a history of diabetes I do not do don't know have at least one first degree relative (parents, sibling, children) who has a history of stroke I reside in Alabama Alaska Arizona Arkansas California Colorado Connecticut Delaware District of Columbia Florida Georgia Hawaii Idaho Illnois Indiana Iowa Kansas Kentucky Louisiana Maine Maryland Massachusetts Michigan Minnesota Mississippi Missouri Montana Nebraska Nevada New Hampshire New Jersey New Mexico New York North Carolina North Dakota Ohio Oklahoma Oregon Pennsylvania Rhode Island South Carolina South Dakota Tennessee Texas Utah Vermont Virginia Washington West Virginia Wisconsin Wyoming don't know I have not have don't know been diagnosed with asthma I have not have don't know been diagnosed with diabetes My diastolic blood pressure (the smaller/bottom number- an average adult's is about 80) is mmHg

I smoke cigarettes per day My spouse smokes cigarettes per day I have 0 or negligible less than 1 1 2 to 3 4 or more don't know drinks per day I travel thousand miles per year in an automobile The driver of the automobile which I most frequently travel in is a male female don't know The age of the driver of the automobile which I most frequently travel in is years I do not do don't know regularly wear seat belts when travelling in a automobile The automobile which I most frequently travel in does not does don't know regularly keep to speeds appropriate to road conditions The driver of the automobile which I most frequently travel in is sometimes never don't know drunk while driving Of the 10 things listed in the Stress List, of them happened to me in the past 12 months I am a sedentary person occasional exerciser conditioning exerciser don't know I work in the mining construction transportation/public utilities agriculture/forestry/fishing public administration manufacturing retail trade services wholesale trade finance/real estate all others don't know industry My father worked in a non-manual manual don't know job My first regular occupation is a non-manual manual don't know job My current occupation is a non-manual manual don't know job Of the 5 types of food in the Dietary Diversity List, on average I consume types more less don't know than 10% of my energy intake comes from fat I am not am don't know among the 15% most depressed of the population I have had sexual partners in the past 12 months For most of my sexual encounters, I do not do don't know use condoms On average, I have hours of sleep a day

Back to Life Calculator Homepage

Originally posted here:
How Long Will I Live? - Life Expectancy Calculator

Read More...

Immune system – New World Encyclopedia

October 23rd, 2015 7:46 pm

The immune system is the system of specialized cells and organs that protects an organism from outside biological influences (though in a broad sense, almost every organ has a protective functionfor example, the tight seal of the skin or the acidic environment of the stomach).

When the immune system is functioning properly, it protects the body against bacteria and viral infections and destroys cancer cells and foreign substances. If the immune system weakens, its ability to defend the body also weakens, allowing pathogens (infectious agents), including viruses that cause common colds and flu, to survive and flourish in the body. Because the immune system also performs surveillance of tumor cells, immune suppression has been reported to increase the risk of certain types of cancer.

The complex coordination of the immune system is stunning. It is capable of recognizing millions of invaders and neutralizing their attacks, and yet at the same time it allows helpful, symbiotic bacteria, such as E. coli, to become established within the human body. From the time of the initial invasion of a foreign element until its removal, the entire immune systemincluding diverse types of white blood cells, each with a different responsibilityharmoniously functions together in recognizing, attacking, and destroying substances identified as foreign.

The immune system is often divided into two sections:

Another way of categorizing this is "nonspecific defenses" (skin, mucous membranes, phagocytes, fever, interferons, cilia, and stomach acid) and "specific defenses" (the cell-mediated and the humoral systems, both of which attack specific pathogens).

The adaptive immune system, also called the "acquired immune system, and "specific immune system," ensures that animals that survive an initial infection by a pathogen are generally immune to further illness caused by that same pathogen. The adaptive immune system is based on dedicated immune cells termed leukocytes (white blood cells).

The basis of specific immunity lies in the capacity of immune cells to distinguish between proteins produced by the body's own cells ("self" antigenthose of the original organism), and proteins produced by invaders or cells under control of a virus ("non-self" antigenor, what is not recognized as the original organism). This distinction is made via T-Cell Receptors (TCR) or B-Cell Receptors (BCR). For these receptors to be efficient they must be produced in thousands of configurations; this way they are able to distinguish between many different invader proteins.

This immense diversity of receptors would not fit in the genome of a cell, and millions of genes, one for each type of possible receptor, would be impractical. Instead, there are a few families of genes, each one having a slightly different modification. Through a special process, unique to cells of jawed vertebrates (Gnathostomata), the genes in these T-cell and B-cell lymphocytes recombine, one from each family, arbitrarily into a single gene.

This way, for example, each antibody or BCR of B lymphocytes has six portions, and is created from two genes unique to this lymphocyte, created by the recombination (union) of a random gene from each family. If there are 6 families, with 50, 30, 9, 40, and 5 members, the total possible number of antibodies is 50x30x6x9x40x5 = 16 million. On top of this there are other complex processes that increase the diversity of BCR or TCR even more, by mutation of the genes in question. The variability of antibodies is practically limitless, and the immune system creates antibodies for any molecule, even artificial molecules that do not exist in nature.

Many TCR and BCR created this way will react with their own peptides. One of the functions of the thymus and bone marrow is to hold young lymphocytes until it is possible to determine which ones react to molecules of the organism itself. This is done by specialized cells in these organs that present the young lymphocytes with molecules produced by them (and effectively the body). All the lymphocytes that react to them are destroyed, and only those that show themselves to be indifferent to the body are released into the bloodstream.

The lymphocytes that do not react to the body number in the millions, each with millions of possible configurations of receptors, each with a receptor for different parts of each microbial protein possible. The vast majority of lymphocytes never find a protein that its receptor is specified for, those few that do find one are stimulated to reproduce. Effective cells are generated with the specific receptor and memory cells. These memory cells are quiescent, they have long lives and are capable of identifying this antigen some time later, multiplying themselves quickly and rapidly responding to future infections.

In many species, the adaptive immune system can be divided into two major sections, the humoral immune system and the cell-mediated immune system.

The humoral immune system acts against bacteria and viruses in the body liquids (e.g., blood) by means of proteins, called immunoglobulins (also known as antibodies), which are produced by B cells. B cells are lymphocytes, with the "B" standing for the bursa of Fabricius, an organ unique to birds, where avian B cells mature. (It does not stand for bone marrow, where B cells are produced in all other vertebrates except for rabbits. B cells were original observed in studies done on immunity in chickens.)

Secreted antibodies bind to antigens on the surfaces of invading microbes (such as viruses or bacteria), which flags them for destruction. An antigen is any substance that causes the immune system to produce antibodies.

Humoral immunity refers to antibody production and all the accessory processes that accompany it: Th2 (T-helper 2 cells) activation and cytokine production (cytokines are proteins that affect the interaction between cells); germinal center formation and isotype switching (switching a specific region of the antibody); and affinity maturation and memory cell generation (memory cell generation has to do with the ability for a body to "remember" a pathogen by producing antibodies specifically targeted for it). Humoral immunity also refers to the effector functions of antibodies, which include pathogen and toxin neutralization, classical complement activation, and opsonin promotion of phagocytosis and pathogen elimination.

The human body has the ability to form millions of different types of B cells each day, and each type has a unique receptor protein, referred to as the B cell receptor (BCR), on its membrane that will bind to one particular antigen. At any one time in the human body there are B cells circulating in the blood and lymph, but are not producing antibodies. Once a B cell encounters its cognate antigen and receives an additional signal from a helper T cell, it can further differentiate into one of two types of B cells.

B cells need two signals to initiate activation. Most antigens are T-dependent, meaning T cell help is required for maximum antibody production. With a T-dependent antigen, the first signal comes from antigen cross linking BCR (B cell receptor) and the second from the Th2 cell. T-dependent antigens present peptides on B cell Class II MHC proteins to Th2 cells. This triggers B cell proliferation and differentiation into plasma cells. Isotype switching to IgG, IgA, and IgE and memory cell generation occur in response to T-dependent antigens.

Some antigens are T-independent, meaning they can deliver both the antigen and the second signal to the B cell. Mice without a thymus (nude or athymic mice) can respond to T-independent antigens. Many bacteria have repeating carbohydrate epitopes that stimulate B cells to respond with IgM synthesis in the absence of T cell help.

T-dependent responses require that B cells and their Th2 cells respond to epitopes on the same antigen. T and B cell epitopes are not necessarily identical. (Once virus-infected cells have been killed and unassembled virus proteins released, B cells specific for internal proteins can also be activated to make opsonizing antibodies to those proteins.) Attaching a carbohydrate to a protein can convert the carbohydrate into a T-dependent antigen; the carbohydrate-specific B cell internalizes the complex and presents peptides to Th2 cells, which in turn activate the B cell to make antibodies specific for the carbohydrate.

An antibody is a large Y-shaped protein used to identify and neutralize foreign objects like bacteria and viruses. Production of antibodies and associated processes constitutes the humoral immune system. Each antibody recognizes a specific antigen unique to its target. This is because at the two tips of its "Y," it has structures akin to locks. Every lock only has one key, in this case, its own antigen. When the key is inserted into the lock, the antibody activates, tagging or neutralizing its target. The production of antibodies is the main function of the humoral immune system.

Immunoglobulins are glycoproteins in the immunoglobulin superfamily that function as antibodies. The terms antibody and immunoglobulin are often used interchangeably. They are found in the blood and tissue fluids, as well as many secretions. In structure, they are globulins (in the -region of protein electrophoresis). They are synthesized and secreted by plasma cells that are derived from the B cells of the immune system. B cells are activated upon binding to their specific antigen and differentiate into plasma cells. In some cases, the interaction of the B cell with a T helper cell is also necessary.

In humans, there are five types: IgA, IgD, IgE, IgG, and IgM. (Ig stands for immunoglobulin.). This is according to differences in their heavy chain constant domains. (The isotypes are also defined with light chains, but they do not define classes, so they are often neglected.) Other immune cells partner with antibodies to eliminate pathogens depending on which IgG, IgA, IgM, IgD, and IgE constant binding domain receptors it can express on its surface.

The antibodies that a single B lymphocyte produces can differ in their heavy chain, and the B cell often expresses different classes of antibodies at the same time. However, they are identical in their specificity for antigen, conferred by their variable region. To achieve the large number of specificities the body needs to protect itself against many different foreign antigens, it must produce millions of B lymphoyctes. In order to produce such a diversity of antigen binding sites for each possible antigen, the immune system would require many more genes than exist in the genome. It was Susumu Tonegawa who showed in 1976 that portions of the genome in B lymphocytes can recombine to form all the variation seen in the antibodies and more. Tonegawa won the Nobel Prize in Physiology or Medicine in 1987 for his discovery.

The cell-mediated immune system, the second main mechanism of the adaptive immune system, destroys virus-infected cells (among other duties) with T cells, also called "T lymphocytes." ("T" stands for thymus, where their final stage of development occurs.)

Cell-mediated immunity is an immune response that does not involve antibodies but rather involves the activation of macrophages and natural killer cells, the production of antigen-specific cytotoxic T-lymphocytes, and the release of various cytokines in response to an antigen. Cellular immunity protects the body by:

Cell-mediated immunity is directed primarily at microbes that survive in phagocytes and microbes that infect non-phagocytic cells. It is most effective in removing virus-infected cells, but also participates in defending against fungi, protozoans, cancers, and intracellular bacteria. It also plays a major role in transplant rejection.

There are two major types of T cells:

In addition, there are regulatory T cells (Treg cells) which are important in regulating cell-mediated immunity.

The adaptive immune system could take days or weeks after an initial infection to have an effect. However, most organisms are under constant assault from pathogens that must be kept in check by the faster-acting innate immune system. Innate immunity, or non-specific defense, defends against pathogens by rapid responses coordinated through chemical or physical barriers or "innate" receptors that recognize a wide spectrum of conserved pathogenic components.

In evolutionary time, it appears that the adaptive immune system developed abruptly in jawed fish. Prior to jawed fish, there is no evidence of adaptive immunity, and animals therefore relied only on their innate immunity. Plants, on the other hand, rely on secondary metabolites (chemical compounds in organisms that are not directly involved in the normal growth, development, or reproduction of organisms) to defend themselves against fungal and viral pathogens as well as insect herbivory. Plant secondary metabolites are derived through vast arrays of plant biosynthetic pathways not needed directly for plant survival, hence why they are named secondary. Plant secondary metabolism should not be confused with innate or adaptive immunity as they evolved along an entirely different evolutionary lineages and rely on entirely different signal cues, pathways, and responses.

The innate immune system, when activated, has a wide array of effector cells and mechanisms. There are several different types of phagocytic cells, which ingest and destroy invading pathogens. The most common phagocytes are neutrophils, macrophages, and dendritic cells. Another cell type, natural killer cells, are especially adept at destroying cells infected with viruses. Another component of the innate immune system is known as the complement system. Complement proteins are normally inactive components of the blood. However, when activated by the recognition of a pathogen or antibody, the various proteins recruit inflammatory cells, coat pathogens to make them more easily phagocytosed, and make destructive pores in the surfaces of pathogens.

The first-line defense includes barriers to infection, such as skin, the mucous coating of the gut, and airways. These physically prevent the interaction between the host and the pathogen. Pathogens that penetrate these barriers encounter constitutively expressed (constantly expressed) anti-microbial molecules (e.g., lysozymes) that restrict the infection.

In addition to the usual defense, the stomach secretes gastric acid, which, in addition to aiding digestive enzymes in the stomach to work on food, prevents bacterial colonization by most pathogens.

The second-line defense includes phagocytic cells (macrophages and neutrophil granulocytes) that can engulf (phagocytose) foreign substances. Macrophages are thought to mature continuously from circulating monocytes.

Phagocytosis involves chemotaxis, where phagocytic cells are attracted to microorganisms by means of chemotactic chemicals such as microbial products, complement, damaged cells, and white blood cell fragments. Chemotaxis is followed by adhesion, where the phagocyte sticks to the microorganism. Adhesion is enhanced by opsonization, where proteins like opsonins are coated on the surface of the bacterium. This is followed by ingestion, in which the phagocyte extends projections, forming pseudopods that engulf the foreign organism. Finally, the bacterium is digested by the enzymes in the lysosome, exposing it to reactive oxygen species and proteases.

In addition, anti-microbial proteins may be activated if a pathogen passes through the barrier offered by skin. There are several classes of antimicrobial proteins, such as acute phase proteins (C-reactive protein, for example, enhances phagocytosis and activates complement when it binds itself to the C-protein of S. pneumoniae ), lysozyme, and the complement system.

The complement system is a very complex group of serum proteins, which is activated in a cascade fashion. Three different pathways are involved in complement activation:

A cascade of protein activity follows complement activation; this cascade can result in a variety of effects, including opsonization of the pathogen, destruction of the pathogen by the formation and activation of the membrane attack complex, and inflammation.

Interferons are also anti-microbial proteins. These molecules are proteins that are secreted by virus-infected cells. These proteins then diffuse rapidly to neighboring cells, inducing the cells to inhibit the spread of the viral infection. Essentially, these anti-microbial proteins act to prevent the cell-to-cell proliferation of viruses.

Earlier studies of innate immunity utilized model organisms that lack adaptive immunity, such as the plant Arabidopsis thaliana, the fly Drosophila melanogaster, and the worm Caenorhabditis elegans. Advances have since been made in the field of innate immunology with the discovery of toll-like receptors (TLRs) and the intracellular nucleotide-binding site leucine-rich repeat proteins (NODs). NODs are receptors in mammal cells that are responsible for a large proportion of the innate immune recognition of pathogens.

In 1989, prior to the discovery of mammalian TLRs, Charles Janeway conceptualized and proposed that evolutionarily conserved features of infectious organisms were detected by the immune system through a set of specialized receptors, which he termed pathogen-associated molecular patterns (PAMPs) and pattern recognition receptors (PRRs), respectively. This insight was only fully appreciated after the discovery of TLRs by the Janeway lab in 1997. The TLRs now comprise the largest family of innate immune receptors (or PRRs). Janeways hypothesis has come to be known as the "stranger model" and substantial debate in the field persists to this day as to whether or not the concept of PAMPs and PRRs, as described by Janeway, is truly suitable to describe the mechanisms of innate immunity. The competing "danger model" was proposed in 1994 by Polly Matzinger and argues against the focus of the stranger model on microbial derived signals, suggesting instead that endogenous danger/alarm signals from distressed tissues serve as the principle purveyors of innate immune responses.

Both models are supported in the later literature, with discoveries that substances of both microbial and non-microbial sources are able to stimulate innate immune responses, which has led to increasing awareness that perhaps a blend of the two models would best serve to describe the currently known mechanisms governing innate immunity.

Splitting the immune system into innate and adaptive systems simplifies discussions of immunology. However, the systems actually are quite intertwined in a number of important respects.

One important example is the mechanisms of "antigen presentation." After they leave the thymus, T cells require activation to proliferate and differentiate into cytotoxic ("killer") T cells (CTLs). Activation is provided by antigen-presenting cells (APCs), a major category of which are the dendritic cells. These cells are part of the innate immune system.

Activation occurs when a dendritic cell simultaneously binds itself to a T "helper" cell's antigen receptor and to its CD28 receptor, which provides the "second signal" needed for DC activation. This signal is a means by which the dendritic cell conveys that the antigen is indeed dangerous, and that the next encountered T "killer" cells need to be activated. This mechanism is based on antigen-danger evaluation by the T cells that belong to the adaptive immune system. But the dendritic cells are often directly activated by engaging their toll-like receptors, getting their "second signal" directly from the antigen. In this way, they actually recognize in "first person" the danger, and direct the T killer attack. In this respect, the innate immune system therefore plays a critical role in the activation of the adaptive immune system.

Adjuvants, or chemicals that stimulate an immune response, provide artificially this "second signal" in procedures when an antigen that would not normally raise an immune response is artificially introduced into a host. With the adjuvant, the response is much more robust. Historically, a commonly-used formula is Freund's Complete Adjuvant, an emulsion of oil and mycobacterium. It was later discovered that toll-like receptors, expressed on innate immune cells, are critical in the activation of adaptive immunity.

Many factors can contribute to the general weakening of the immune system:

Despite high hopes, there are no medications that directly increase the activity of the immune system. Various forms of medication that activate the immune system may cause autoimmune disorders.

Suppression of the immune system is often used to control autoimmune disorders or inflammation when this causes excessive tissue damage, and to prevent transplant rejection after an organ transplant. Commonly used immunosuppressants include glucocorticoids, azathioprine, methotrexate, ciclosporin, cyclophosphamide, and mercaptopurine. In organ transplants, ciclosporin, tacrolimus, mycophenolate mofetil, and various others are used to prevent organ rejection through selective T cell inhibition.

The most important function of the human immune system occurs at the cellular level of the blood and tissues. The lymphatic and blood circulation systems are highways for specialized white blood cells to travel around the body. Each white blood cell type (B cells, T cells, natural killer cells, and macrophages) has a different responsibility, but all function together with the primary objective of recognizing, attacking, and destroying bacteria, viruses, cancer cells, and all substances seen as foreign. Without this coordinated effort, a person would not be able to survive more than a few days before succumbing to overwhelming infection.

Infections set off an alarm that alerts the immune system to bring out its defensive weapons. Natural killer cells and macrophages rush to the scene to consume and digest infected cells. If the first line of defense fails to control the threat, antibodies, produced by the B cells, upon the order of T helper cells, are custom-designed to hone in on the invader.

Many disorders of the human immune system fall into two broad categories that are characterized by:

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.

Original post:
Immune system - New World Encyclopedia

Read More...

Laser Eye Treatment Center – Centre For Sight

October 23rd, 2015 7:45 pm

Have you been thinking of laser vision correction? Shed your doubts, concerns, specs and contact lenses, because blade free LASIK has arrived. With this technology, laser vision correction procedure has become 100 percent blade-free and completely safe.

In any LASIK procedure the first step is to create a corneal flap. In standard LASIK the surgeon uses a hand-held oscillating blade called microkeratome to cut the corneal flap. The flap is then folded and the Excimer laser treats the cornea to correct the refractive error.

In blade free LASIK, femtosecond laser has replaced the steel blade for creation of the corneal flap which improves visual outcome and post-operative comfort for the patient.

When you opt for advanced blade free LASIK procedure you get a completely integrated, personalized vision correction procedure based on cutting edge technology at every step. NASA recommends blade free LASIK to aspiring astronauts to get rid of their specs, as it can withstand high gravitational forces and has been found to be stable and secure even in extreme environmental conditions.

Advantages Precise corneal flap results in improved visual outcome Safer than standard LASIK Treats patients with high refractive errors and thin corneas too.

For people with nearsightedness (myopia), farsightedness (hyperopia) or astigmatism, LASIK surgery could be the key to a life free of bulky spectacles or contact lenses. But not everybody is a suitable candidate for this type of laser eye surgery. Here are the few main questions a LASIK surgeon is likely to ask you during a consultation.

Centre for Sight is equipped with trained and experienced eye specialists to help the patients in dealing of respective issues with specialization and care with advanced Blade-free LASIK surgery. This laser eye treatment creates flap in Blade-free LASIK which reduces risk of an irregular flap. You can trust our renowned eye specialists for Lasik eye surgery which is one of the Lasik Treatment in India.

View original post here:
Laser Eye Treatment Center - Centre For Sight

Read More...

Life and Death in Terms of Embryonic Stem Cells

October 23rd, 2015 7:45 pm

Since the beginning of time, mankind has pondered the question of what it means to be alive. When, precisely, can one be considered a human being? With the advent of stem cell research, we are forced to confront this question head-on. Human embryonic stem cells have enormous medical potential; by harnessing the power of their undifferentiated state, we may be able to cure diseases and disabilities that have plagued mankind for millennia. Rather than simply treating the symptoms of debilitating conditions, we may be able to attack the diseases at their source, working from within the body itself. However, obtaining embryonic stem cells, despite the many benefits that may result, poses many new ethical questions. Embryonic stem cells are generated during the early stages of the formation of a human embryo. These cells adhere to the wall of the blastocyst and, in the process of obtaining them, the embryo is destroyed. The ethical dilemma is this; does this tiny but powerful group of cells constitute a human life, and, if so, it is justifiable to take it in order to save others?

What are Embryonic Stem Cells?

A fertilized embryo must undergo a series of divisions in order to grow. There are many different types of cells in an adult human, but, with the exception of red blood cells and lymph cells, every cell in the human body contains an identical genome. [5] If all cells contain an identical DNA sequence and originate from the same source, how does each cell know what to become? The answer lies in a population of cells known as stem cells. To be classified as a stem cell requires the possession of two key abilities

Unlike somatic cells, stem cells begin, not with a single fate, but in an undifferentiated state. This initial lack of specificity is crucial, for their division has the ability to field more unspecified cells or ones that will eventually become any cell in the organism. [3] The earliest stem cells are known as totipotent, meaning that they have the ability to differentiate into any cell in the embryo or the resulting adult. As the cells divide, they progressively lose their totipotent abilities, becoming more and more specified. The egg-sperm unit divides every 12-18 hours; first from two cells into four, then eight, then sixteen. [5] After this third cell division, totipotent cells give rise to pluripotent stem cells, which can become nearly any cell in the body. The unit is now a hollow ball known as a blastula, and with pluripotent cells adhered to the wall in a clump known as the Inner Cell Mass. The wall will become the supportive placenta as the embryo grows, with the ICM becoming the embryo itself. [7] As the pluripotent cells divide, they develop into cells called Lineage Restricted Stem Cells, then Progenitor Cells, and finally Differentiated Cells with pre-determined function. [See Figure 1] Each time the cell divides, it becomes more highly specified, and less plastic in terms of medical potential.

Why use Embryonic Stem Cells?

Because of their unique ability to generate so many different kinds of cells, and potential to reside in several areas of the human body, stem cells may eventually establish themselves as a cornerstone of 21st century medicine. Stem cell research has created an entirely new branch of medicine, called Regenerative Medicine. The specialty of this new discipline would be to repair organs or tissues affected or destroyed by age, disease or injury. [5] [6] [10] In at least one instance, experimental techniques have been highly successful. Scientists have developed large sheets of epidermal cells, which can be used to repair burns that have destroyed the full thickness of the skin. [10] Researchers are hoping to branch out and use the self-renewal and differentiating abilities of embryonic stem cells to treat diseases such as Parkinsons Disease or Type 1 Diabetes, or even paralysis resulting from damage to the spinal cord. [5] The hope is to learn to culture the cells and to manipulate their differentiation prior to inserting them into a patient. The cells would, in theory, be used to repair or re-grow the damaged tissues without being rejected by the patients immune system. In diabetic patients, the cells may be used to replace non-functioning pancreatic cells, while in paraplegic individuals the cells may replace the damaged components of the spine, allowing them to walk again.

An Ethical Mess: Are we taking a life in order to give life?

Obtaining embryonic stem cells for research purposes invariably results in the destruction of the embryo. Many individuals pose the question of whether this constitutes taking one human beings life in order to preserve the life of another. Currently, there are five major views concerning whether this ball of cells is in fact alive. Each viewpoint suggests that ones life begins at a different point in development.

Genetic View: Fertilization

Embryological View: Gastrulation A second position posits that one becomes human at gastrulation. [5] [12] Between 12 and 14 days after fertilization, the embryo begins to form germ layers, which will eventually develop into the three major tissue types found in adults. [17] Scientists view this as a turning point in development for, at the onset of gastrulation, the embryo can no longer divide to form twins. [12] If it survives, it is committed to forming a single individual. The blastula, now called a gastrula, develops three distinct layers of cells; the ectoderm, the mesoderm and the endoderm. The outermost layer, the ectoderm, will develop into the central nervous system, hair, fingernails and the epidermis of the skin. The endoderm, the innermost layer, gives rise to the lining of the digestive and respiratory tracts, and the glands such as the pancreas and liver. The mesoderm, the middle layer, is perhaps the most diverse, for it will eventually yield the muscles, the gonads, cartilage and the circulatory system, to name only a few. [17] Cells that are beginning to form the germ layers are too far along the differentiation pathway to be as useful as their predecessors. Considering the embryo to be alive only once gastrulation occurs is consistent with views in favor of Embryonic Stem Cell research. If one chooses this viewpoint, experimenting with embryos prior to this would not constitute taking a human life, for researchers would be obtaining the cells much earlier than the time of gastrulation.

Neurological View: EEG Activity The third major viewpoint is that human life begins with the acquisition of recognizable brain activity. At approximately, 24 weeks of age, there is a sufficient amount of coherence in the fetus developing brain that its activity can be seen via an electroencephalogram (EEG). [5] [18] In the United States, death is often determined by brain function. As stated in the Uniform Determination of Death Act, so-called brain death is defined as when the entire brain ceas[es] to function, irreversibly. The entire brain includes the brain stem, as well as the neocortex. The concept of entire brain distinguishes determination of death under this Act from neocortical death or persistent vegetative state. " [16] An individual whose cardiovascular and respiratory systems still function, but who produces no brain activity is considered to be dead. The fetal heart beat is present from approximately 7 weeks of gestational age, [4] but brain activity is not present until 24 weeks. This follows the logic present in US law; if we choose to define death in terms of the cessation of brain activity, we may choose to define life by its onset. This position also supports the use of stem-cell research, as the cells would be obtained months before the commencement of any recognizable brain activity.

Ecological View: Survival A fourth standpoint in terms of human life is viability. Some individuals choose to define human life as the point where the fetus is viable outside the mothers womb. [18] This has often been determined by lung function, as the respiratory system is both crucial for survival and one of the last systems to finish developing in the human fetus. Development of the lungs begins as early as week 4 of gestation, and continues until birth with the proliferation of the alveolar sacs. [8] [14] Surfactant, a compound produced in the alveoli beginning at about 34 weeks of age, reduces surface tension in the lungs and allows them to expand. Without this compound, infants have severely decreased lung function, which may prove fatal. Premature infants also have underdeveloped brain and immune function, which makes them highly susceptible to both apnea and infection as well as a host of other health problems. [14] Historically, many infants born before 28 weeks of age were unable to survive. [5] However, with the continued development of neonatal intensive care and cardio-pulmonary life support, the cutoff line for viability has become increasingly blurred. One is now forced to question whether a neonate born at 25 weeks of age with severely impaired brain and body function and kept alive only with assistance of machines is truly living.

The Birth View

Conclusion

Stem cells hold a power never before seen in medicine. If properly controlled, they may allow us to fight diseases that are now considered incurable. Their use, however, remains highly controversial, owing to the destruction of embryos in the process. Advocates against embryonic stem-cell research and use argue that the tiny ball of cells inside the blastula is alive. These individuals take the Fertilization viewpoint, maintaining that a human, no matter how small, is still a human. To them, the use of embryonic stem cells, even to save many others, can never justify the destruction of a human life. Supporters of embryonic stem cells maintain that zygotes are not truly human prior to gastrulation, brain function or even birth itself. Use of the inner cell mass in its earliest stages does not constitute ethical wrongdoing. The cells are obtained so early that the mass does not yet possess any human qualities, such as differentiated tissues or brain function. These individuals also point out that the majority of the blastocysts being used would not survive to begin with, and that anti-stem cell groups should see that the ends justify the means. Clearly stem cells have many potential benefits for mankind, but at the moment they are surrounded by a controversy that is unlikely to resolve itself any time soon. In the future, perhaps we will find a way to manipulate differentiated cells to have undifferentiated properties, thereby avoiding the ethics of embryonic stem cell use. However, until that day arrives, we must continue to ask ourselves the question of what it means to be human.

More:
Life and Death in Terms of Embryonic Stem Cells

Read More...

Cell Therapy & Regenerative Medicine – University of Utah …

October 23rd, 2015 11:42 am

About Us

Learn more about Cell Therapy & Regenerative Medicine.

What is a Neurosphere?

CTRM provides services to develop and manufacture novel cellular therapy.

The Cell Therapy and Regenerative Medicine Program (CTRM) at the University of Utah provides the safest, highest quality products for therapeutic use and research. Our goals are to facilitate the availability of cellular and tissue based therapies to patients by bridging efforts in basic research, bioengineering and the medical sciences. As well as assemble the expertise and infrastructure to address the complex regulatory, financial and manufacturing challenges associated with delivering cell and tissue based products to patients.

To support hematopoietic stem cell transplants and to deliver innovative cellular and tissue engineered products to patients by providing comprehensive bench to bedside services that coordinate the efforts of clinicians, researchers, and bioengineers.

Product quality, safety and efficacy; Optimization of resource utilization; Promotion of productive collaborations; Support of innovative products; and Adherence to scientific and ethical excellence.

The Center of Excellence for the state of Utah that translates cutting-edge cell therapy and engineered tissue based research into clinical products that extend and improve the quality of life of individuals suffering from debilitating diseases and injuries.

Original post:
Cell Therapy & Regenerative Medicine - University of Utah ...

Read More...

Policy & Ethics – Issues in Genetics

October 22nd, 2015 11:43 am

Feature HHS announces proposal to update rules governing research on study participant

Medical advances wouldn't be possible without individuals willing to volunteer to participate in research. Today's proposed changes to the Common Rule for protecting human research participants would update safeguards for participants and reduce unnecessary administrative burdens. For more information and details on providing comments on the proposed rule, go to: HHS News Release Read the Notice of Proposed Rulemaking [federalregister.gov]

The use of human subjects in the field of genomics raises a number of key policy considerations that are being addressed at NHGRI and elsewhere. Learn more about his important topic with a new fact sheet from the Policy and Program Analysis Branch. Read more

NIH has issued a position statement on the use of public or private cloud systems for storing and analyzing controlled-access genomic data under the NIH Genomic Data Sharing (GDS) Policy. Read the Position Statement

This fall, Cari Young, Sc.M., and Julie Nadel, Ph.D., will join the National Human Genome Research Institute as American Society of Human Genetics (ASHG)/National Human Genome Research Institute (NHGRI) education and public policy fellows. Ms. Young will spend time working with NHGRI's Policy and Program Analysis Branch, while Dr. Nadel will direct her talents to the Education and Community Involvement Branch. Both credit their high school biology classes with inspiring the direction of their careers. Read more

Last Updated: September 17, 2015

Follow this link:
Policy & Ethics - Issues in Genetics

Read More...

Preimplantation genetic diagnosis – Wikipedia, the free …

October 22nd, 2015 11:43 am

Pre-implantation genetic diagnosis (PGD or PIGD) refers to genetic profiling of embryos prior to implantation (as a form of embryo profiling), and sometimes even of oocytes prior to fertilization. PGD is considered in a similar fashion to prenatal diagnosis. When used to screen for a specific genetic disease, its main advantage is that it avoids selective pregnancy termination as the method makes it highly likely that the baby will be free of the disease under consideration. PGD thus is an adjunct to assisted reproductive technology, and requires in vitro fertilization (IVF) to obtain oocytes or embryos for evaluation. The term preimplantation genetic screening (PGS) is used to denote procedures that do not look for a specific disease but use PGD techniques to identify embryos at risk. The PGD allows studying the DNA of eggs or embryos to select those that carry certain damaging characteristics. It is useful when there are previous chromosomal or genetic disorders in the family and within the context of in vitro fertilization programs. [1]

The procedures may also be called preimplantation genetic profiling to adapt to the fact that they are sometimes used on oocytes or embryos prior to implantation for other reasons than diagnosis or screening.[2]

Procedures performed on sex cells before fertilization may instead be referred to as methods of oocyte selection or sperm selection, although the methods and aims partly overlap with PGD.

In 1967, Robert Edwards and Richard Gardner reported the successful identification of the sex of rabbit blastocysts.[3] It was not until the 1980s that human IVF was fully developed, which coincided with the breakthrough of the highly sensitive polymerase chain reaction (PCR) technology. Handyside and collaborators' first successful tests happened in October 1989, with the first births in 1990[4] though the preliminary experiments had been published some years earlier.[5][6] In these first cases, PCR was used for sex determination of patients carrying X-linked diseases.

PGD became increasingly popular during the 1990s when it was used to determine a handful of severe genetic disorders, such as sickle-cell anemia, Tay Sachs disease, Duchennes muscular dystrophy, and Beta-thalassemia.[7]

As with all medical interventions associated with human reproduction, PGD raises strong, often conflicting opinions of social acceptability, particularly due to its eugenic implications. In some countries, such as Germany,[8] PGD is permitted for only preventing stillbirths and genetic diseases, in other countries PGD is permitted in law but its operation is controlled by the state.[clarification needed]

PGD can potentially be used to select embryos to be without a genetic disorder, to have increased chances of successful pregnancy, to match a sibling in HLA type in order to be a donor, to have less cancer predisposition, and for sex selection.

PGD is available for a large number of monogenic disorders that is, disorders due to a single gene only (autosomal recessive, autosomal dominant or X-linked) or of chromosomal structural aberrations (such as a balanced translocation). PGD helps these couples identify embryos carrying a genetic disease or a chromosome abnormality, thus avoiding diseased offspring. The most frequently diagnosed autosomal recessive disorders are cystic fibrosis, Beta-thalassemia, sickle cell disease and spinal muscular atrophy type 1. The most common dominant diseases are myotonic dystrophy, Huntington's disease and Charcot-Marie-Tooth disease; and in the case of the X-linked diseases, most of the cycles are performed for fragile X syndrome, haemophilia A and Duchenne muscular dystrophy. Though it is quite infrequent, some centers report PGD for mitochondrial disorders or two indications simultaneously.

PGD is also now being performed in a disease called Hereditary multiple exostoses (MHE/MO/HME).

In addition, there are infertile couples who carry an inherited condition and who opt for PGD as it can be easily combined with their IVF treatment.

Preimplantation genetic profiling (PGP) has been suggested as a method to determine embryo quality in in vitro fertilization, in order to select an embryo that appears to have the greatest chances for successful pregnancy. However, as the results of PGP rely on the assessment of a single cell, PGP has inherent limitations as the tested cell may not be representative of the embryo because of mosaicism.[9]

A systematic review and meta-analysis of existing randomized controlled trials came to the result that there is no evidence of a beneficial effect of PGP as measured by live birth rate.[9] On the contrary, for women of advanced maternal age, PGP significantly lowers the live birth rate.[9] Technical drawbacks, such as the invasiveness of the biopsy, and chromosomal mosaicism are the major underlying factors for inefficacy of PGP.[9]

Alternative methods to determine embryo quality for prediction of pregnancy rates include microscopy as well as profiling of RNA and protein expression.

Human leukocyte antigen (HLA) typing of embryos, so that the child's HLA matches a sick sibling, availing for cord-blood stem cell donation.[10] The child is in this sense a "savior sibling" for the recipient child. HLA typing has meanwhile become an important PGD indication in those countries where the law permits it.[11] The HLA matching can be combined with the diagnosis for monogenic diseases such as Fanconi anaemia or beta thalassemia in those cases where the ailing sibling is affected with this disease, or it may be exceptionally performed on its own for cases such as children with leukaemia. The main ethical argument against is the possible exploitation of the child, although some authors maintain that the Kantian imperative is not breached since the future donor child will not only be a donor but also a loved individual within the family.

A more recent application of PGD is to diagnose late-onset diseases and (cancer) predisposition syndromes. Since affected individuals remain healthy until the onset of the disease, frequently in the fourth decade of life, there is debate on whether or not PGD is appropriate in these cases. Considerations include the high probability of developing the disorders and the potential for cures. For example, in predisposition syndromes, such as BRCA mutations which predispose the individual to breast cancer, the outcomes are unclear. Although PGD is often regarded as an early form of prenatal diagnosis, the nature of the requests for PGD often differs from those of prenatal diagnosis requests made when the mother is already pregnant. Some of the widely accepted indications for PGD would not be acceptable for prenatal diagnosis.

Preimplantation genetic diagnosis provides a method of prenatal sex discernment even before implantation, and may therefore be termed preimplantation sex discernment. Potential applications of preimplantation sex discernment include:

In the case of families at risk for X-linked diseases, patients are provided with a single PGD assay of gender identification. Gender selection offers a solution to individuals with X-linked diseases who are in the process of getting pregnant. The selection of a female embryo offspring is used in order to prevent the transmission of X-linked Mendelian recessive diseases. Such X-linked Mendelian diseases include Duchenne muscular dystrophy (DMD), and hemophilia A and B, which are rarely seen in females because the offspring is unlikely to inherit two copies of the recessive allele. Since two copies of the mutant X allele are required for the disease to be passed on to the female offspring, females will at worst be carriers for the disease but may not necessarily have a dominant gene for the disease. Males on the other hand only require one copy of the mutant X allele for the disease to occur in one's phenotype and therefore, the male offspring of a carrier mother has a 50% chance of having the disease. Reasons may include the rarity of the condition or because affected males are reproductively disadvantaged. Therefore, medical uses of PGD for selection of a female offspring to prevent the transmission of X-linked Mendelian recessive disorders are often applied. Preimplantation genetic diagnosis applied for gender selection can be used for non-Mendelian disorders that are significantly more prevalent in one sex. Three assessments are made prior to the initiation of the PGD process for the prevention of these inherited disorders. In order to validate the use of PGD, gender selection is based on the seriousness of the inherited condition, the risk ratio in either sex, or the options for disease treatment.[12]

A 2006 survey reveals that PGD has occasionally been used to select an embryo for the presence of a particular disease or disability, such as deafness, in order that the child would share that characteristic with the parents.[2]

PGD is a form of genetic diagnosis performed prior to implantation. This implies that the patients oocytes should be fertilized in vitro and the embryos kept in culture until the diagnosis is established. It is also necessary to perform a biopsy on these embryos in order to obtain material on which to perform the diagnosis. The diagnosis itself can be carried out using several techniques, depending on the nature of the studied condition. Generally, PCR-based methods are used for monogenic disorders and FISH for chromosomal abnormalities and for sexing those cases in which no PCR protocol is available for an X-linked disease. These techniques need to be adapted to be performed on blastomeres and need to be thoroughly tested on single-cell models prior to clinical use. Finally, after embryo replacement, surplus good quality unaffected embryos can be cryopreserved, to be thawed and transferred back in a next cycle.

Currently, all PGD embryos are obtained by assisted reproductive technology, although the use of natural cycles and in vivo fertilization followed by uterine lavage was attempted in the past and is now largely abandoned. In order to obtain a large group of oocytes, the patients undergo controlled ovarian stimulation (COH). COH is carried out either in an agonist protocol, using gonadotrophin-releasing hormone (GnRH) analogues for pituitary desensitisation, combined with human menopausal gonadotrophins (hMG) or recombinant follicle stimulating hormone (FSH), or an antagonist protocol using recombinant FSH combined with a GnRH antagonist according to clinical assessment of the patients profile (age, body mass index (BMI), endocrine parameters). hCG is administered when at least three follicles of more than 17mm[verification needed] mean diameter are seen at transvaginal ultrasound scan. Transvaginal ultrasound-guided oocyte retrieval is scheduled 36 hours after hCG administration. Luteal phase supplementation consists of daily intravaginal administration of 600g of natural micronized progesterone.

Oocytes are carefully denudated from the cumulus cells, as these cells can be a source of contamination during the PGD if PCR-based technology is used. In the majority of the reported cycles, intracytoplasmic sperm injection (ICSI) is used instead of IVF. The main reasons are to prevent contamination with residual sperm adhered to the zona pellucida and to avoid unexpected fertilization failure. The ICSI procedure is carried out on mature metaphase-II oocytes and fertilization is assessed 1618 hours after. The embryo development is further evaluated every day prior to biopsy and until transfer to the womans uterus. During the cleavage stage, embryo evaluation is performed daily on the basis of the number, size, cell-shape and fragmentation rate of the blastomeres. On day 4, embryos were scored in function of their degree of compaction and blastocysts were evaluated according to the quality of the throphectoderm and inner cell mass, and their degree of expansion.

As PGD can be performed on cells from different developmental stages, the biopsy procedures vary accordingly. Theoretically, the biopsy can be performed at all preimplantation stages, but only three have been suggested: on unfertilised and fertilised oocytes (for polar bodies, PBs), on day three cleavage-stage embryos (for blastomeres) and on blastocysts (for trophectoderm cells).

The biopsy procedure always involves two steps: the opening of the zona pellucida and the removal of the cell(s). There are different approaches to both steps, including mechanical, chemical, and physical (Tyrodes acidic solution) and laser technology for the breaching of the zona pellucida, extrusion or aspiration for the removal of PBs and blastomeres, and herniation of the trophectoderm cells.

A polar body biospy is the sampling of a polar body, which is a small haploid cell that is formed concomitantly as an egg cell during oogenesis, but which generally does not have the ability to be fertilized. Compared to a blastocyst biopsy, a polar body biopsy can potentially be of lower costs, less harmful side-effects, and more sensitive in detecting abnormalities.[13] The main advantage of the use of polar bodies in PGD is that they are not necessary for successful fertilisation or normal embryonic development, thus ensuring no deleterious effect for the embryo. One of the disadvantages of PB biopsy is that it only provides information about the maternal contribution to the embryo, which is why cases of autosomal dominant and X-linked disorders that are maternally transmitted can be diagnosed, and autosomal recessive disorders can only partially be diagnosed. Another drawback is the increased risk of diagnostic error, for instance due to the degradation of the genetic material or events of recombination that lead to heterozygous first polar bodies.

Cleavage-stage biopsy is generally performed the morning of day three post-fertilization, when normally developing embryos reach the eight-cell stage. The biopsy is usually performed on embryos with less than 50% of anucleated fragments and at an 8-cell or later stage of development. A hole is made in the zona pellucida and one or two blastomeres containing a nucleus are gently aspirated or extruded through the opening. The main advantage of cleavage-stage biopsy over PB analysis is that the genetic input of both parents can be studied. On the other hand, cleavage-stage embryos are found to have a high rate of chromosomal mosaicism, putting into question whether the results obtained on one or two blastomeres will be representative for the rest of the embryo. It is for this reason that some programs utilize a combination of PB biopsy and blastomere biopsy. Furthermore, cleavage-stage biopsy, as in the case of PB biopsy, yields a very limited amount of tissue for diagnosis, necessitating the development of single-cell PCR and FISH techniques. Although theoretically PB biopsy and blastocyst biopsy are less harmful than cleavage-stage biopsy, this is still the prevalent method. It is used in approximately 94% of the PGD cycles reported to the ESHRE PGD Consortium. The main reasons are that it allows for a safer and more complete diagnosis than PB biopsy and still leaves enough time to finish the diagnosis before the embryos must be replaced in the patients uterus, unlike blastocyst biopsy. Of all cleavage-stages, it is generally agreed that the optimal moment for biopsy is at the eight-cell stage. It is diagnostically safer than the PB biopsy and, unlike blastocyst biopsy, it allows for the diagnosis of the embryos before day 5. In this stage, the cells are still totipotent and the embryos are not yet compacting. Although it has been shown that up to a quarter of a human embryo can be removed without disrupting its development, it still remains to be studied whether the biopsy of one or two cells correlates with the ability of the embryo to further develop, implant and grow into a full term pregnancy.

Not all methods of opening the zona pellucida have the same success rate because the well-being of the embryo and/or blastomere may be impacted by the procedure used for the biopsy. Zona drilling with acid Tyrodes solution (ZD) was looked at in comparison to partial zona dissection (PZD) to determine which technique would lead to more successful pregnancies and have less of an effect on the embryo and/or blastomere. ZD uses a digestive enzyme like pronase which makes it a chemical drilling method. The chemicals used in ZD may have a damaging effect on the embryo. PZD uses a glass microneedle to cut the zona pellucida which makes it a mechanical dissection method that typically needs skilled hands to perform the procedure. In a study that included 71 couples, ZD was performed in 26 cycles from 19 couples and PZD was performed in 59 cycles from 52 couples. In the single cell analysis, there was a success rate of 87.5% in the PZD group and 85.4% in the ZD group. The maternal age, number of oocytes retrieved, fertilization rate, and other variables did not differ between the ZD and PZD groups. It was found that PZD led to a significantly higher rate of pregnancy (40.7% vs 15.4%), ongoing pregnancy (35.6% vs 11.5%), and implantation (18.1% vs 5.7%) than ZD. This suggests that using the mechanical method of PZD in blastomere biopsies for preimplantation genetic diagnosis may be more proficient than using the chemical method of ZD. The success of PZD over ZD could be attributed to the chemical agent in ZD having a harmful effect on the embryo and/or blastomere. Currently, zona drilling using a laser is the predominant method of opening the zona pellucida. Using a laser is an easier technique than using mechanical or chemical means. However, laser drilling could be harmful to the embryo and it is very expensive for in vitro fertilization laboratories to use especially when PGD is not a prevalent process as of modern times. PZD could be a viable alternative to these issues.[14]

In an attempt to overcome the difficulties related to single-cell techniques, it has been suggested to biopsy embryos at the blastocyst stage, providing a larger amount of starting material for diagnosis. It has been shown that if more than two cells are present in the same sample tube, the main technical problems of single-cell PCR or FISH would virtually disappear. On the other hand, as in the case of cleavage-stage biopsy, the chromosomal differences between the inner cell mass and the trophectoderm (TE) can reduce the accuracy of diagnosis, although this mosaicism has been reported to be lower than in cleavage-stage embryos.

TE biopsy has been shown to be successful in animal models such as rabbits,[15] mice[16] and primates.[17] These studies show that the removal of some TE cells is not detrimental to the further in vivo development of the embryo.

Human blastocyst-stage biopsy for PGD is performed by making a hole in the ZP on day three of in vitro culture. This allows the developing TE to protrude after blastulation, facilitating the biopsy. On day five post-fertilization, approximately five cells are excised from the TE using a glass needle or laser energy, leaving the embryo largely intact and without loss of inner cell mass. After diagnosis, the embryos can be replaced during the same cycle, or cryopreserved and transferred in a subsequent cycle.

There are two drawbacks to this approach, due to the stage at which it is performed. First, only approximately half of the preimplantation embryos reach the blastocyst stage. This can restrict the number of blastocysts available for biopsy, limiting in some cases the success of the PGD. Mc Arthur and coworkers[18] report that 21% of the started PGD cycles had no embryo suitable for TE biopsy. This figure is approximately four times higher than the average presented by the ESHRE PGD consortium data, where PB and cleavage-stage biopsy are the predominant reported methods. On the other hand, delaying the biopsy to this late stage of development limits the time to perform the genetic diagnosis, making it difficult to redo a second round of PCR or to rehybridize FISH probes before the embryos should be transferred back to the patient.

Sampling of cumulus cells can be performed in addition to a sampling of polar bodies or cells from the embryo. Because of the molecular interactions between cumulus cells and the oocyte, gene expression profiling of cumulus cells can be performed to estimate oocyte quality and the efficiency of an ovarian hyperstimulation protocol, and may indirectly predict aneuploidy, embryo development and pregnancy outcomes.[19][19]

Fluorescent in situ hybridization (FISH) and Polymerase chain reaction (PCR) are the two commonly used, first-generation technologies in PGD. PCR is generally used to diagnose monogenic disorders and FISH is used for the detection of chromosomal abnormalities (for instance, aneuploidy screening or chromosomal translocations). Over the past few years, various advancements in PGD testing have allowed for an improvement in the comprehensiveness and accuracy of results available depending on the technology used.[20] Recently a method was developed allowing to fix metaphase plates from single blastomeres. This technique in conjunction with FISH, m-FISH can produce more reliable results, since analysis is done on whole metaphase plates[21]

In addition to FISH and PCR, single cell genome sequencing is being tested as a method of preimplantation genetic diagnosis.[22] This characterizes the complete DNA sequence of the genome of the embryo.

FISH is the most commonly applied method to determine the chromosomal constitution of an embryo. In contrast to karyotyping, it can be used on interphase chromosomes, so that it can be used on PBs, blastomeres and TE samples. The cells are fixated on glass microscope slides and hybridised with DNA probes. Each of these probes are specific for part of a chromosome, and are labelled with a fluorochrome. Currently, a large panel of probes are available for different segments of all chromosomes, but the limited number of different fluorochromes confines the number of signals that can be analysed simultaneously.

The type and number of probes that are used on a sample depends on the indication. For sex determination (used for instance when a PCR protocol for a given X-linked disorder is not available), probes for the X and Y chromosomes are applied along with probes for one or more of the autosomes as an internal FISH control. More probes can be added to check for aneuploidies, particularly those that could give rise to a viable pregnancy (such as a trisomy 21). The use of probes for chromosomes X, Y, 13, 14, 15, 16, 18, 21 and 22 has the potential of detecting 70% of the aneuploidies found in spontaneous abortions.

In order to be able to analyse more chromosomes on the same sample, up to three consecutive rounds of FISH can be carried out. In the case of chromosome rearrangements, specific combinations of probes have to be chosen that flank the region of interest. The FISH technique is considered to have an error rate between 5 and 10%.

The main problem of the use of FISH to study the chromosomal constitution of embryos is the elevated mosaicism rate observed at the human preimplantation stage. A meta-analysis of more than 800 embryos came to the result that approximately 75% of preimplantation embryos are mosaic, of which approximately 60% are diploidaneuploid mosaic and approximately 15% aneuploid mosaic.[23] Li and co-workers[24] found that 40% of the embryos diagnosed as aneuploid on day 3 turned out to have a euploid inner cell mass at day 6. Staessen and collaborators found that 17.5% of the embryos diagnosed as abnormal during PGS, and subjected to post-PGD reanalysis, were found to also contain normal cells, and 8.4% were found grossly normal.[25] As a consequence, it has been questioned whether the one or two cells studied from an embryo are actually representative of the complete embryo, and whether viable embryos are not being discarded due to the limitations of the technique.

Kary Mullis conceived PCR in 1985 as an in vitro simplified reproduction of the in vivo process of DNA replication. Taking advantage of the chemical properties of DNA and the availability of thermostable DNA polymerases, PCR allows for the enrichment of a DNA sample for a certain sequence. PCR provides the possibility to obtain a large quantity of copies of a particular stretch of the genome, making further analysis possible. It is a highly sensitive and specific technology, which makes it suitable for all kinds of genetic diagnosis, including PGD. Currently, many different variations exist on the PCR itself, as well as on the different methods for the posterior analysis of the PCR products.

When using PCR in PGD, one is faced with a problem that is inexistent in routine genetic analysis: the minute amounts of available genomic DNA. As PGD is performed on single cells, PCR has to be adapted and pushed to its physical limits, and use the minimum amount of template possible: which is one strand. This implies a long process of fine-tuning of the PCR conditions and a susceptibility to all the problems of conventional PCR, but several degrees intensified. The high number of needed PCR cycles and the limited amount of template makes single-cell PCR very sensitive to contamination. Another problem specific to single-cell PCR is the allele drop out (ADO) phenomenon. It consists of the random non-amplification of one of the alleles present in a heterozygous sample. ADO seriously compromises the reliability of PGD as a heterozygous embryo could be diagnosed as affected or unaffected depending on which allele would fail to amplify. This is particularly concerning in PGD for autosomal dominant disorders, where ADO of the affected allele could lead to the transfer of an affected embryo.

The establishment of a diagnosis in PGD is not always straightforward. The criteria used for choosing the embryos to be replaced after FISH or PCR results are not equal in all centres. In the case of FISH, in some centres only embryos are replaced that are found to be chromosomally normal (that is, showing two signals for the gonosomes and the analysed autosomes) after the analysis of one or two blastomeres, and when two blastomeres are analysed, the results should be concordant. Other centres argue that embryos diagnosed as monosomic could be transferred, because the false monosomy (i.e. loss of one FISH signal in a normal dipoloid cell) is the most frequently occurring misdiagnosis. In these cases, there is no risk for an aneuploid pregnancy, and normal diploid embryos are not lost for transfer because of a FISH error. Moreover, it has been shown that embryos diagnosed as monosomic on day 3 (except for chromosomes X and 21), never develop to blastocyst, which correlates with the fact that these monosomies are never observed in ongoing pregnancies.

Diagnosis and misdiagnosis in PGD using PCR have been mathematically modelled in the work of Navidi and Arnheim and of Lewis and collaborators.[26][27] The most important conclusion of these publications is that for the efficient and accurate diagnosis of an embryo, two genotypes are required. This can be based on a linked marker and disease genotypes from a single cell or on marker/disease genotypes of two cells. An interesting aspect explored in these papers is the detailed study of all possible combinations of alleles that may appear in the PCR results for a particular embryo. The authors indicate that some of the genotypes that can be obtained during diagnosis may not be concordant with the expected pattern of linked marker genotypes, but are still providing sufficient confidence about the unaffected genotype of the embryo. Although these models are reassuring, they are based on a theoretical model, and generally the diagnosis is established on a more conservative basis, aiming to avoid the possibility of misdiagnosis. When unexpected alleles appear during the analysis of a cell, depending on the genotype observed, it is considered that either an abnormal cell has been analysed or that contamination has occurred, and that no diagnosis can be established. A case in which the abnormality of the analysed cell can be clearly identified is when, using a multiplex PCR for linked markers, only the alleles of one of the parents are found in the sample. In this case, the cell can be considered as carrying a monosomy for the chromosome on which the markers are located, or, possibly, as haploid. The appearance of a single allele that indicates an affected genotype is considered sufficient to diagnose the embryo as affected, and embryos that have been diagnosed with a complete unaffected genotype are preferred for replacement. Although this policy may lead to a lower number of unaffected embryos suitable for transfer, it is considered preferable to the possibility of a misdiagnosis.

Preimplantation genetic haplotyping (PGH) is a PGD technique wherein a haplotype of genetic markers that have statistical associations to a target disease are identified rather than the mutation causing the disease.[28]

Once a panel of associated genetic markers have been established for a particular disease it can be used for all carriers of that disease.[28] In contrast, since even a monogenic disease can be caused by many different mutations within the affected gene, conventional PGD methods based on finding a specific mutation would require mutation-specic tests. Thus, PGH widens the availability of PGD to cases where mutation-specific tests are unavailable.

PGH also has an advantage over FISH in that FISH is not usually able to make the differentiation between embryos that possess the balanced form of a chromosomal translocation and those carrying the homologous normal chromosomes. This inability can be seriously harmful to the diagnosis made. PGH can make the distinction that FISH often cannot. PGH does this by using polymorphic markers that are better suited at recognizing translocations. These polymorphic markers are able to distinguish between embryos that carried normal, balanced, and unbalanced translocations. FISH also requires more cell fixation for analysis whereas PGH requires only transfer of cells into polymerase chain reaction tubes. The cell transfer is a simpler method and leaves less room for analysis failure.[29]

Embryo transfer is usually performed on day three or day five post-fertilization, the timing depending on the techniques used for PGD and the standard procedures of the IVF centre where it is performed.

With the introduction in Europe of the single-embryo transfer policy, which aims at the reduction of the incidence of multiple pregnancies after ART, usually one embryo or early blastocyst is replaced in the uterus. Serum hCG is determined at day 12. If a pregnancy is established, an ultrasound examination at 7 weeks is performed to confirm the presence of a fetal heartbeat. Couples are generally advised to undergo PND because of the, albeit low, risk of misdiagnosis.

It is not unusual that after the PGD, there are more embryos suitable for transferring back to the woman than necessary. For the couples undergoing PGD, those embryos are very valuable, as the couple's current cycle may not lead to an ongoing pregnancy. Embryo cryopreservation and later thawing and replacement can give them a second chance to pregnancy without having to redo the cumbersome and expensive ART and PGD procedures.

PGD/PGS is an invasive procedure that requires a serious consideration, according to Michael Tucker, Ph.D., Scientific Director and Chief Embryologist at Georgia Reproductive Specialists in Atlanta.[30] One of the risks of PGD includes damage to the embryo during the biopsy procedure (which in turn destroys the embryo as a whole), according to Serena H. Chen, M.D., a New Jersey reproductive endocrinologist with IRMS Reproductive Medicine at Saint Barnabas.[30] Another risk is cryopreservation where the embryo is stored in a frozen state and thawed later for the procedure. About 20% of the thawed embryos do not survive.[31][32] There has been a study indicating a biopsied embryo has a less rate of surviving cryopreservation.[33] Another study suggests that PGS with cleavage-stage biopsy results in a significantly lower live birth rate for women of advanced maternal age.[34] Also, another study recommends the caution and a long term follow-up as PGD/PGS increases the perinatal death rate in multiple pregnancies.[35]

In a mouse model study, PGD has been attributed to various long term risks including a weight gain and memory decline; a proteomic analysis of adult mouse brains showed significant differences between the biopsied and the control groups, of which many are closely associated with neurodegenerative disorders like Alzheimers and Down Syndrome.[36]

PGD has raised ethical issues, although this approach could reduce reliance on fetal deselection during pregnancy. The technique can be used for prenatal sex discernment of the embryo, and thus potentially can be used to select embryos of one sex in preference of the other in the context of "family balancing". It may be possible to make other "social selection" choices in the future that introduce socio-economic concerns. Only unaffected embryos are implanted in a womans uterus; those that are affected are either discarded or donated to science.[37]

PGD has the potential to screen for genetic issues unrelated to medical necessity, such as intelligence and beauty, and against negative traits such as disabilities. The medical community has regarded this as a counterintuitive and controversial suggestion.[38] The prospect of a "designer baby" is closely related to the PGD technique, creating a fear that increasing frequency of genetic screening will move toward a modern eugenics movement.[39] On the other hand, a principle of procreative beneficence is proposed, which is a putative moral obligation of parents in a position to select their children to favor those expected to have the best life.[40] An argument in favor of this principle is that traits (such as empathy, memory, etc.) are "all-purpose means" in the sense of being of instrumental value in realizing whatever life plans the child may come to have.[41]

In 2006 three percent of PGD clinics in the US reported having selected an embryo for the presence of a disability.[42] Couples involved were accused of purposely harming a child. This practice is notable in dwarfism, where parents intentionally create a child who is a dwarf.[42] In the selection of a saviour sibling to provide a matching bone marrow transplant for an already existing affected child, there are issues including the commodification and welfare of the donor child.[43]

By relying on the result of one cell from the multi-cell embryo, PGD operates under the assumption that this cell is representative of the remainder of the embryo. This may not be the case as the incidence of mosaicism is often relatively high.[44] On occasion, PGD may result in a false negative result leading to the acceptance of an abnormal embryo, or in a false positive result leading to the deselection of a normal embryo.

Another problematic case is the cases of desired non-disclosure of PGD results for some genetic disorders that may not yet be apparent in a parent, such as Huntington disease. It is applied when patients do not wish to know their carrier status but want to ensure that they have offspring free of the disease. This procedure can place practitioners in questionable ethical situations, e.g. when no healthy, unaffected embryos are available for transfer and a mock transfer has to be carried out so that the patient does not suspect that he/she is a carrier. The ESHRE ethics task force currently recommends using exclusion testing instead. Exclusion testing is based on a linkage analysis with polymorphic markers, in which the parental and grandparental origin of the chromosomes can be established. This way, only embryos are replaced that do not contain the chromosome derived from the affected grandparent, avoiding the need to detect the mutation itself.[citation needed]

Intersex people are born with physical sex characteristics that don't meet stereotypical binary notions of male or female; such traits are stigmatized for largely cosmetic reasons.[45] PGD allows discrimination against those with with intersex traits. Georgiann Davis argues that such discrimination fails to recognize that many people with intersex traits led full and happy lives.[46]Morgan Carpenter highlights the appearance of several intersex variations in a list by the Human Fertilisation and Embryology Authority of "serious" "genetic conditions" that may be de-selected in the UK, including 5 alpha reductase deficiency and androgen insensitivity syndrome, traits evident in elite women athletes and "the world's first openly intersex mayor".[47]Organisation Intersex International Australia has called for the Australian National Health and Medical Research Council to prohibit such interventions, noting a "close entanglement of intersex status, gender identity and sexual orientation in social understandings of sex and gender norms, and in medical and medical sociology literature".[48]

In 2015, the Council of Europe published an Issue Paper on Human rights and intersex people, remarking:

Some religious organizations disapprove of this procedure. The Roman Catholic Church, for example, takes the position that it involves the destruction of human life.[50] and besides that, opposes the necessary in vitro fertilization of eggs as contrary to Aristotelian principles of nature.[citation needed] The Jewish Orthodox religion believes the repair of genetics is okay, but they do not support making a child that is genetically fashioned[37]

A meta-analysis that was performed indicates research studies conducted in PGD underscore future research. This is due to positive attitudinal survey results, postpartum follow-up studies demonstrating no significant differences between those who had used PGD and those who conceived naturally, and ethnographic studies which confirmed that those with a previous history of negative experiences found PGD as a relief. Firstly, in the attitudinal survey, women with a past history of infertility, pregnancy termination, and repeated miscarriages reported having a more positive attitude towards preimplantation genetic diagnosis. They were more accepting towards pursuing PGD. Secondly, likewise to the first attitudinal study, an ethnographic study conducted in 2004 found similar results. Couples with a past history of multiple miscarriages, infertility, and an ill child, felt that preimplantation genetic diagnosis was a viable option. They also felt more relief; "those using the technology were actually motivated to not repeat pregnancy loss".[51] In summary, although some of these studies are limited due to their retrospective nature and limited samples, the study's results indicate an overall satisfaction of participants for the use of PGD. However, the authors of the studies do indicate that these studies emphasize the need for future research such as creating a prospective design with a valid psychological scale necessary to assess the levels of stress and mood during embryonic transfer and implantation.[51]

Prior to implementing the Assisted Human Reproduction Act (AHR) in 2004, PGD was unregulated in Canada. The Act banned sex selection for non-medical purposes.[52]

Due to 2012s national budget cuts, the AHR was removed. The regulation of assisted reproduction was then delegated to each province.[53] This delegation provides provinces with a lot of leeway to do as they please. As a result, provinces like Quebec, Alberta and Manitoba have put almost the full costs of IVF on the public healthcare bill.[54] Dr. Santiago Munne, developer of the first PGD test for Downs Syndrome and founder of Reprogenetics, saw these provincial decisions as an opportunity for his company to grow and open more Reprogenetics labs around Canada. He dismissed all controversies regarding catalogue babies and states that he had no problem with perfect babies.[55]

Ontario, however, has no concrete regulations regarding PGD. Since 2011, the Ministry of Children and Youth Services in Ontario advocates for the development government-funded safe fertility education, embryo monitoring and assisted reproduction services for all Ontarians. This government report shows that Ontario not only has indefinite regulations regarding assisted reproduction services like IVF and PGD, but also does not fund any of these services. The reproductive clinics that exist are all private and located only in Brampton, Markham, Mississauga, Scarborough, Toronto, London and Ottawa.[56] In contrast, provinces such as Alberta and Quebec not only have more clinics, but have also detailed laws regarding assisted reproduction and government funding for these practices.

Before 2010, the usage of PGD was in a legal grey area.[57] In 2010, the Federal Court of Justice of Germany ruled that PGD can be used in exceptional cases.[57] On 7 July 2011, the Bundestag passed a law that allows PGD in certain cases. The procedure may only be used when there is a strong likelihood that parents will pass on a genetic disease, or when there is a high genetic chance of a stillbirth or miscarriage.[8] On 1 February 2013, the Bundesrat approved a rule regulating how PGD can be used in practice.[57]

In Hungary, PGD is allowed in case of severe hereditary diseases (when genetic risk is above 10%). The preimplantation genetic diagnosis for aneuploidy (PGS/PGD-A) is an accepted method as well. It is currently recommended in case of multiple miscarriages, and/or several failed IVF treatments, and/or when the mother is older than 35 years.[58] Despite being an approved method, PGD-A is available at only one Fertility Clinic in Hungary.[59]

In India, Ministry of Family Health and Welfare, regulates the concept under - "The Pre-Conception and Prenatal Diagnostic Techniques (Prohibition of Sex Selection) Act, 1994". The Act was further been revised after 1994 and necessary amendment were made are updated timely on the official website of the Indian Government dedicated for the cause.[60]

In South Africa, where the right to reproductive freedom is a constitutionally protected right, it has been proposed that the state can only limit PGD to the degree that parental choice can harm the prospective child or to the degree that parental choice will reinforce societal prejudice.[61]

The preimplantation genetic diagnosis is allowed in Ukraine and from November 1, 2013 is regulated by the order of the Ministry of health of Ukraine "On approval of the application of assisted reproductive technologies in Ukraine" from 09.09.2013 787. [3].

In the UK, assisted reproductive technologies are regulated under the Human Fertilization and Embryology Act (HFE) of 2008. However, the HFE Act does not address issues surrounding PGD. Thus, the HFE Authority (HFEA) was created in 2003 to act as a national regulatory agency which issues licenses and monitors clinics providing PGD. The HFEA only permits the use of PGD where the clinic concerned has a licence from the HFEA and sets out the rules for this licensing in its Code of Practice ([4]). Each clinic, and each medical condition, requires a separate application where the HFEA check the suitability of the genetic test proposed and the staff skills and facilities of the clinic. Only then can PGD be used for a patient.

The HFEA strictly prohibits sex selection for social or cultural reasons, but allows it to avoid sex-linked disorders. They state that PGD is not acceptable for, "social or psychological characteristics, normal physical variations, or any other conditions which are not associated with disability or a serious medical condition." It is however accessible to couples or individuals with a known family history of serious genetic diseases.[62] Nevertheless, the HFEA regards intersex variations as a "serious genetic disease", such as 5-alpha-reductase deficiency, a trait associated with some elite women athletes.[63] Intersex advocates argue that such decisions are based on social norms of sex gender, and cultural reasons.[64]

No uniform system for regulation of assisted reproductive technologies, including genetic testing, exists in the United States. The practice and regulation of PGD most often falls under state laws or professional guidelines as the federal government does not have direct jurisdiction over the practice of medicine. To date, no state has implemented laws directly pertaining to PGD, therefore leaving researchers and clinicians to abide to guidelines set by the professional associations. The Center for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC) states that all clinics providing IVF must report pregnancy success rates annually to the federal government, but reporting of PGD use and outcomes is not required. The American Society for Reproductive Medicine (ASRM) states that, "PGD should be regarded as an established technique with specific and expanding applications for standard clinical practice." They also state, "While the use of PGD for the purpose of preventing sex-linked diseases is ethical, the use of PGD solely for sex selection is discouraged."[65]

In a study of 135 IVF clinics, 88% had websites, 70% mentioned PGD and 27% of the latter were university- or hospital-based and 63% were private clinics. Sites mentioning PGD also mentioned uses and benefits of PGD far more than the associated risks. Of the sites mentioning PGD, 76% described testing for single-gene diseases, but only 35% mentioned risks of missing target diagnoses, and only 18% mentioned risks for loss of the embryo. 14% described PGD as new or controversial. Private clinics were more likely than other programs to list certain PGD risks like for example diagnostic error, or note that PGD was new or controversial, reference sources of PGD information, provide accuracy rates of genetic testing of embryos, and offer gender selection for social reasons.[66]

Read the rest here:
Preimplantation genetic diagnosis - Wikipedia, the free ...

Read More...

Gene therapy | Cancer Research UK

October 22nd, 2015 11:41 am

Researchers are looking at different ways of using gene therapy, including

Some types of gene therapy aim to boost the body's natural ability to attack cancer cells. Our immune system has cells that recognise and kill harmful things that can cause disease, such as cancer cells.

There are many different types of immune cell. Some of them produce proteins that encourage other immune cells to destroy cancer cells. Some types of therapy add genes to a patient's immune cells to make them better at finding or destroying particular types of cancer. There are a few trials using this type of gene therapy in the UK.

Some gene therapies put genes into cancer cells to make the cells more sensitive to particular treatments such as chemotherapy or radiotherapy. This type of gene therapy aims to make the other cancer treatments work better.

Some types of gene therapy deliver genes into the cancer cells that allow the cells to change drugs from an inactive form to an active form. The inactive form of the drug is called a pro drug.

After giving the carrier containing the gene, the doctor gives the patient the pro drug. The pro drug may be a tablet or capsule that you swallow, or you may have it into the bloodstream.

The pro drug circulates in the body and doesn't harm normal cells. But when it reaches the cancer cells, the gene activates it and the drug kills the cancer cells.

Some gene therapies block processes that cancer cells use to survive. For example, most cells in the body are programmed to die if their DNA is damaged beyond repair. This is called programmed cell death or apoptosis. But cancer cells block this process so they don't die even when they are supposed to. Some gene therapy strategies aim to reverse this blockage. Doctors hope that these new types of treatment will make the cancer cells die.

Some viruses infect and kill cells. Researchers are working on ways to change these viruses so that they only target and kill cancer cells, leaving healthy cells alone. This sort of treatment uses the viruses to kill cancer cells directly rather than to deliver genes. So it is not cancer gene therapy in the true sense of the word. But doctors sometimes refer to it as gene therapy.

One example of this type of research uses the cold sore virus (herpes simplex virus). The changed virus is called Oncovex. It has been tested in early clinical trials for advanced melanoma, pancreatic cancer and head and neck cancers.

Read the rest here:
Gene therapy | Cancer Research UK

Read More...

Alabama Ortopaedics & Sports Medicine Associates, P. C.

October 22nd, 2015 9:42 am

Welcome to Alabama Orthopaedic & Sports Medicine Associates, P.C.

Alabama Orthopaedic & Sports Medicine Associates. P.C is a purpose-built facility for Sports Medicine and General Orthopaedic care servicing Montgomery and entire Alabama. Dr. Kenneth Taylor, our director is a Board Certified Orthopaedic Surgeon specializing in Sports Medicine and Family Orthopaedics.

Our website features interactive presentations on the anatomy of Hip and Knee joints, Total Hip Replacement, Hip Resurfacing, Revision Hip Replacement, Knee Arthroscopy, ACL Reconstruction Unicondylar Knee Replacement, Revision Knee Replacement and much more. Website also features topics on Shoulders, hand, wrist, back & spine, foot & ankle, sports medicine and much more.

The information in this website is provided to reinforce the advice you receive from your own doctors and is not intended to replace discussions with your doctor. We hope you find our website Informative and Interactive to meet your inquiries.

Thank you for visiting us.

Click here to find out more about us.

Read the original post:
Alabama Ortopaedics & Sports Medicine Associates, P. C.

Read More...

Page 1,167«..1020..1,1661,1671,1681,169..1,1801,190..»


2025 © StemCell Therapy is proudly powered by WordPress
Entries (RSS) Comments (RSS) | Violinesth by Patrick